Skip to main content

Extract from my book The Philosophy Gym - "The Consciousness Conundrum"


13. The Consciousness Conundrum

Philosophy Gym category:

Warm up
Moderate

More challenging


Scientists are grappling with “the problem of consciousness”: the problem of explaining how that walnut-shaped lump of grey matter between your ears is capable of producing a rich inner world of conscious experiences. Will they ever solve this mystery? Some think it’s only a matter of time. Yet there are arguments that appear to show that consciousness is something that it is in principle impossible for science to explain.

The private realm of consciousness

Take a look at something red: a ripe tomato, for example. As you look at this object, you are conscious of having a certain experience – a colour experience. As the philosopher Thomas Nagel[i] (xx) explains, there’s something it is like to have this experience, something for you, the subject.
            We spend our lives immersed in a vibrant flow of such experiences: the smell of a flower, the taste of an orange, the rough sensation of wood under ones fingertips, a zinging pain, a melancholic moment. An interesting feature of this rich inner life we lead is that it seems peculiarly hidden from others. Others can observe my body and outward behaviour. But my experiences are hidden inside. Indeed, they would appear to be “hidden inside” in very strong sense. For they are not physically hidden, as, say, my brain is physically hidden inside my skull. Things that are physically hidden can in principle be revealed. Surgeons might one day be able to open up my skull and observe what physically goes on inside me when I have a colour experience. But they can never enter my mind and observe what the experience is like for me, from my point of view.


What is it like to be a bat?
            There are also conscious experiences no human being has ever enjoyed. Take bats for example. Bats manage to find their way around in the dark by using echo-location. The bat emits a sound (inaudible to humans), and the loudness of the echoes and the direction from which they come allow the bat to build up a picture of its environment.

[SUGGESTED ILLUSTRATION: BAT EMITTING SOUND (SEMI-CIRCLES) AND THEN HEARING THE ECHO BOUNCING BACK (MORE SEMI-CIRCLES)]

Echo-location allows bats to “see” using sound. Now ask yourself: What must it be like to be a bat, to experience the world as the bat does? No doubt there is something it’s like for the bat when it “sees” using echo-location, but, as Nagel points out, we can’t know what it’s like. We could discover everything there is to know about what happens in a bat’s nervous system when it “sees” using sound. But that still wouldn’t allow us to know what the experience is like for the bat. It seems the bat’s experience, like yours and mine, is essentially private.
The realm of conscious experience is responsible for what continues to be one of the most profound and intractable of mysteries, a mystery with which both philosophers and scientists are currently very much engaged. The mystery concerns how our physical bodies and our conscious minds are related. The problem, as we shall see, is that, on the one hand, it seems your conscious mind must be physical, yet, on the other hand, it seems it cannot be.

Two competing theories of consciousness

Scientists tell us that when you looked at that red object a minute or so ago, the following happened. Light of certain wavelengths was reflected off the object into your eye where it was focused onto your retina to produce an image. Your retina is covered with millions of light sensitive cells, some of which are sensitive to differences in wavelength. The light falling on to these cells caused them to emit electrical impulses which then flowed down the nerves linking your eye to the back of your brain. That caused something to happen in your brain.
            But what about your experience? According to the philosopher René Descartes (1596-1650) your conscious mind is a distinct entity capable of existing on its own, independently of anything physical. So, on Descartes’ view, after something happened in your brain, something else had to happen: your brain caused something to happen in your mind. Your mind and brain may interact. But they are not identical.

[ILLUSTRATE]

According to many contemporary scientists and philosophers, however, it’s a mistake to think of conscious experience in this way. Professor Susan Greenfield, for example, insists that “you are your brain”. Your experience isn’t something extra – something on top of what happens physically. Rather, the mental just is part of what’s going on physically.

[ILLUSTRATE]

            Certainly, scientists sometimes reveal that what might seem like two distinct things are actually one and the same thing. Take the morning star and the evening star, for example. For a long time, we thought these heavenly bodies were distinct. Then astronomers discovered that they are one and the same object seen twice over (the planet Venus).
Scientists have also established that certain properties are identical. For example, they have discovered that heat is a molecular motion, electricity is a flow of electrons and water is H2O.
So why shouldn’t it also turn out that pain just is a certain state of the brain? Admittedly, pain doesn’t seem like a brain state. But so what? After all, heat doesn’t seem like molecular motion – yet that’s just what it is.

Substances and properties

We have been looking at two competing theories about consciousness. First, there are those who believe that your conscious experiences are nothing over and above what goes on in your brain. Second, there are those who, like Descartes, deny this. But before we get to the arguments for and against these two positions, it will be useful if we distinguish two rather different versions of the second position.
On Descartes’s view, your mind and body are distinct substances: each is capable of existing independently of the other. Your conscious mind could, in principle, be detached from everything physical and exist on its own. This position is called substance dualism.
Hardly any scientists or philosophers are now prepared to accept substance dualism. But there are still plenty of philosophers (and at least some scientists) around who believe that there are two distinct and irreducible kinds of property: physical properties and mental properties. This position is called property dualism.
According to property dualism, there’s only one kind of stuff – physical stuff. But objects made out of this physical stuff can have two quite different sorts of property. On the view of the property dualist, there are both mental properties and physical properties: the mental properties of a human being are extra properties that exist in addition to all of his or her physical properties.

An argument against dualism

            Let’s now turn to one of the most popular arguments against all forms of dualism.
In effect, dualists want to introduce an extra layer of facts in addition to the physical facts. There are physical facts: the facts about physical substances and properties. But according to dualists, there are also non-physical substances and/or properties. The facts about these non-physical substances/properties are facts in addition to the physical facts.
Many scientists and philosophers consider the suggestion that there are such “additional” facts thoroughly unscientific. Why is this?
Suppose that at a dinner party I am given the choice between a glass of wine and a glass of beer.
[ILLUSTRATE: “WINE OR BEER?”]

I like both, but decide on this occasion to have wine. I reach out and select a glass of white.
Scientists tell us that such physical movements have physical causes. The movement of my arm was caused by the action of muscles in my arm, which was itself brought about by electrical activity in the efferent nerves running from my brain.

[ILLUSTRATE]

This electrical activity was in turn caused by physical activity in my brain, which was caused brought about by further preceding physical causes, including the stimulation of my nervous system by light reflected off the glasses on the tray in front of me and the sound of someone speaking to me. These physical causes in turn had physical causes, which in turn had physical causes, and so on.
Indeed, it seems that if scientists were furnished with knowledge of the laws of nature plus all the physical facts about my body and my environment as they were, say, one minute prior to my deciding to reach out and grasp that glass of wine, it would be possible in principle for them to figure out that my arm would do what it did. That movement of my arm was fixed in advance by how things stood physically.
But if this is correct – if what happens physically is fixed in advance by the preceding physical facts – then there is no possibility of any non-physical fact affecting how things turn out. The non-physical must be causally irrelevant to what goes on physically.
But if dualism is true, then my conscious mind is non-physical. But then it follows that my mind can make no difference to what goes on physically. Suppose, for example, that I had decided to pick up a glass of beer instead. Because of the physical facts, my arm would have been compelled to reach out and grasped that glass of wine anyway.

ILLUSTRATE: THINK BUBBLE “BUT I WANTED A GLASS OF BEER”]

Indeed, if dualism is true, you could take my mind away altogether and my body would still carry on in exactly the same way.
But this is absurd, surely? My mind can and does affect how my body behaves. But as it is only the physical facts that affect how things turn out physically, the only way in which the facts about what happens in my mind can have a physical effect is if they are themselves physical facts. But then it follows that dualism (both substance and property) is false.

 

Many scientists and philosophers are convinced by this and other arguments that the facts about what goes on in the conscious mind must ultimately be physical facts. However, the issue is far from settled. There are also powerful arguments that appear to show that these scientists and philosophers are mistaken. One of the best known arguments is presented by the philosopher Frank Jackson. Jackson’s argument runs as follows.

Mary and the black and white room

            A girl called “Mary” is born. Before she has any visual experiences, Mary is placed in a black and white room by scientists who wish to study her. The scientists arrange that Mary never has a colour experience (they hide Mary’s pink hands from her by using white gloves, and so on). Mary experiences only black, white and shades of grey.

[ILLUSTRATION: MARY IN HER ROOM.]

Mary grows up in her black and white environment. She develops a fascination with science. Indeed Mary eventually becomes the world’s greatest brain expert. She finds out everything there is to know about what goes on inside a human brain when the human experiences the colour red. She discovers all the physical facts about the brains of colour perceivers: how their neurones are firing, how the brain chemistry is balanced, and so on.
            Then, one day, one of the scientists studying her brings a ripe tomato into her black and white world.
Mary is stunned. She now has an experience that she’s never had before. She finds out what it is like to have a colour experience. Mary discovers a new fact: the fact that the experience of red is like this (I’m looking at that red object again). But Mary previously knew all the physical facts. So the fact that the experience is like this is not a physical fact. Facts about the qualitative character of our conscious experiences – about what it is like to have them – are not physical facts.

The explanatory gap

Jackson seems to have shown that there are more facts than just the physical facts. But there’s a further conclusion you might wish to draw. Jackson’s story also appears to show that not everything can be explained or understood by science. We can’t explain or understand why red things look like this by appealing only to the physical facts about us. We come up against what contemporary philosophers call an explanatory gap at this point.
Contrast the case of heat. Identifying heat with vigorous molecular motion allows us to deduce the various properties of heat. Discovering what’s going on at the molecular level allows us to understand why objects that are heated char and blacken, why they tend to make nearby objects hot, and so on.
But a full understanding of the goings-on in the human brain will not allow one to understand why pain feels the way it does or explain why ripe tomatoes produce this sort of visual experience. Mary knows everything there is to know about what goes on in the brains of colour perceivers, but this knowledge does not allow her to understand what an experience of red is actually like. Indeed, none of the physical facts she discovers go any way towards explaining why such physiological states should be accompanied by conscious states at all.

The analogy with life

Jackson’s argument appears to show both that
(1) There are more facts than the physical facts,
and
(2) It is in principle impossible for the physical sciences to account for consciousness.

But many scientists are dismissive of such conclusions. They often suggest the current situation with respect to consciousness is similar to the situation 200 years ago with respect to life.  Life at that time constituted a great mystery. We simply had no idea how mere physical matter could be organized in such a way as to produce an animate, living thing. Many thought that something extra – a mysterious and supernatural “life force” –had to be added to a physical object in order to imbue it with life.
Today, of course, the explanation of life is mostly within our grasp. Darwin’s theory of natural selection, advances in genetics, and so on have allowed us to explain many of the properties of life. Even where a scientific explanation of some particular feature of life currently eludes us, we can at least now see how such an explanation might in principle be constructed just by appealing to physical facts.
Many scientists argue that, similarly, just because a scientific explanation of consciousness now eludes us doesn’t mean that no such explanation is possible. There’s no need to suppose that consciousness must be something mysterious and supernatural that exists in addition to what we find within the natural, physical world. These are early days in the scientific investigation of consciousness. Our current inability to imagine how consciousness might be explained by appealing only to physical facts may simply be due to our lack of an adequate theory, just as in the case of life.

Conclusion: a mystery

We have been grappling with mystery of how to accommodate consciousness within the physical universe. Many scientists believe that consciousness must ultimately be reducible to and explicable in terms of the physical. Indeed, given that the conscious mind is able causally to affect what goes on physically, it seems it must itself be physical.
But there are powerful objections to this belief. Jackson’s story about Mary and the black and white room seems to show that it is in principle impossible for the facts about the character of our conscious experience to be reduced to and explained in terms of physical facts. It seems there must be more facts than just the physical.
Many scientists reject all forms of dualism out of hand. But unless they can show what is wrong with Jackson’s argument (and, indeed, the other very convincing looking-arguments that are around), their dismissive attitude towards dualism looks hasty. Blindly to reject such arguments looks more like prejudice than a rationally held position.
Of course, it may be that there’s something wrong with Jackson’s argument (see the text box below). But the onus is on those who reject all forms of dualism to show precisely what is wrong with it. And of course, showing what’s wrong with such arguments is the job not of empirical science, but of logic and the philosophy.
So can science ever solve the mystery of consciousness? The answer is, perhaps. But not by itself. Science will need the help of philosophy.

[[START OF BIG TEXT BOX (DOUBLE PAGE SPREAD?)

THINKING TOOLS: The masked man fallacy

This section explains what may be wrong with Jackson’s argument. There is a popular form of argument often used to establish that two things are not identical. You search for a property that one of the two things has that the other lacks. If you can find such a property, it follows that the items in question are non-identical.
For example, if you want to establish that K2 and Everest are distinct mountains, all you need to do is find a property one mountain possesses that the other lacks. For example, you might argue like this:

Everest has the property of being over 29,000ft high
K2 doesn’t have the property of being over 29,000ft high
Therefore: Everest is not identical with K2

This is a sound argument: each of the two premises is true and the logic is impeccable. The argument really does establish that Everest and K2 are distinct.
Those who argue that mind and body are non-identical often appeal to the same form of argument. Here, for example, is an argument (often attributed to Descartes) called the argument from doubt.
            I don’t doubt that I exist. After all, by trying to doubt that I exist, I demonstrate that I do exist, so my attempt at doubting that I exist must inevitably be self-defeating.
            I do doubt that my body exists. It seems to me that I might be a disembodied mind, with all my experiences being generated by some sort of malevolent demon (for more on this sort of doubt, see chapter XX “Brainsnatched”).
But then it seems that my body has a property that I lack: my body has the property of being something the existence of which I doubt. I lack this property. So it surely follows – by an argument analogous to that about Everest and K2 – that I’m not identical with my body. Here’s the argument laid out more formally:

My body possesses the property of being something the existence of which I doubt
I don’t possess the property of being something the existence of which I doubt
Therefore: I am not identical with my body.

This sort of argument has convinced many that mind and body are non-identical. But, despite the similarity to the Everest/K2 argument, this is a bad argument. What we have here is an example of the masked man fallacy. Here’s another example of the fallacy. Suppose I witness a bank being robbed. This leads me to believe that the masked man robbed the bank. Later, detectives inform me that their lead suspect is my father. Horrified, I try to prove that my father cannot be the masked man. I point out that the masked man has a property my father lacks: he’s someone I believe to have robbed the bank. I argue like this:

The masked man has the property of being someone I believe robbed the bank
My father lacks the property of being someone I believe robbed the bank
Therefore: my father is not identical with the masked man.

This is obviously a bad argument, despite sharing the same form as the sound Everest/K2 argument. It could yet turn out that my father is the masked man, despite the fact that both premises are true. Why is this?
The problem is that this form of argument does not work for all kinds of property. It works for properties such as being more than 29,000ft high. It does not work with properties such as being someone I believe to have robbed the bank. More generally, this form of argument is invalid whenever the property in question involves someone’s psychological attitude towards a thing.
For example, in the masked man case, I try to show that my father and the masked man are distinct by pointing out that I have an attitude towards one that I don’t have towards the other: I believe one robbed the bank but not the other. But such attitudes are incapable of revealing whether or not the items in question really are distinct. Here are a couple of other examples:

John Wayne is someone John knows appeared in “True Grit”
Marion Morrison is not someone John knows appeared in “True Grit”
Therefore: John Wayne isn’t Marion Morrison

Heat is widely recognised to cook food
Molecular motion is not widely recognised to cook food
Therefore: heat isn’t molecular motion

Both these arguments have true premises but false conclusions (“John Wayne” is the stage name of Marion Morrison). The problem, again, is that what someone may know or believe or recognise about one thing but not another is not the sort of property one can use to establish the non-identity of those things. The argument from doubt involves the same fallacy.
What of Jackson’s argument about Mary? Does it also involve the masked man fallacy? I think that, as it stands, it does. But you should check for yourself. Of course, none of this is to say that I believe dualism is now defeated. There may be better arguments for dualism than Jackson’s, arguments that don’t involve the masked man fallacy. [END OF TEXT BOX (FULL PAGE?)]

What to read next?

This chapter might usefully be read in conjunction with chapter XX “Could a Machine Think?” Look for where some of the arguments overlap.
In chapter XX “Do We Ever Deserve to be Punished?” I briefly discuss the discovery that the universe is not after all governed by strict and exceptionless laws, but merely by probabilistic laws. So it turns out that the most that someone furnished with full information about my physical body and environment could ever predict about my future behaviour is what I will probably do. After reading chapter XX, you might wish to return to this chapter to consider the question: Does this discovery undermine the argument against dualism presented above? Even if it does, might some version of that argument still be salvaged?

Further Reading

Jackson’s story about Mary and the black and white room appears in:
·      “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, in W. Lycan (ed.), Mind and Cognition (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990).
For a breezy and yet quite thorough introduction to the problem of consciousness, see:
·      David Papineau and Howard Selina, Introducing Consciousness (Cambridge: Icon, 2000).
An interesting collection of pieces on the mind can be found in the now quite old but nevertheless still excellent:
·      Douglas R. Hofstadter and Daniel Dennett (eds.), The Mind’s I (London: Penguin, 1981).
The Mind’s I includes Thomas Nagel’s famous paper, “What is it Like to be a Bat?” [also included as chpt 38 of Nigel Warburton (ed.), Philosophy: Basic Readings (London: Routledge, 1999)].


[i] See Tomas Nagel, “What is it Like to be a Bat?”, in Douglas R. Hofstadter and Daniel Dennett (eds.), The Mind’s I (London: Penguin, 1981)

Comments

Aojamaru said…
spealing of philosopy.....i have a question
i had a conversation with an "presupptionalist" apologist Jason Lisle a little while and do you think this is stright up question begging

Jason Lisle:“No. Again, we can know that the revelation is from God because any alternative would make knowledge impossible. And we do have knowledge. Thus, the revelation is from God.”

Me:you are begging the question,

Dr. Lisle: No, it is a valid modus tollens.

This guy is in outright denial right?

Thanks
Lothars Sohn said…
Hello folks.


Article of Stephen Law: I certainly agree with this basic thought and believe it is very well illustrated by the argument of Thomas Nagel about the feelings of a bat.

https://lotharlorraine.wordpress.com/?s=bat


Aojamaru: presupositionalists have never, never been able to show that "Biblical Christianity" is the only coherent worldview making sense of knowledge.
Actually, since the Bible is demonstrably full of contradictions, their own worldview is incoherent and self-contradictory.
And I say that as a Christian myself.


Cheers.
Philip Rand said…
Consciousness....hmmmmm, an interesting problem...

What is so interesting about it...is that when goes through the myriad of definitions of what constitutes reality...one invariably comes back to the problem of consciousness...

Strange really, when on realises one uses only 0.045% of ones brain for cognition...

What is interesting...is that even if one is purely materialist (classical) on this issue one is still faced with perplexing results, i.e. if one assumes the existence of "particles"...one finds that "particles" are not strictly inside ones body.

Say, someone wants to measure a particle's position in ones brain, there is a non-zero probability of detecting it in the remotest places of the universe.

Nagel's bat is interesting...but, I would say that if a bat can laugh (most mammals laugh)...then this would perhaps give me an insight as to what is going on in the bat's mind....
Philip Rand said…
Lothars

I had a read of your article you posted...I found it interesting...

But, I would say that underneath the "mental" and the "material" they are the same.

The former is a qualitative question about the world...and the latter is a quantitative question about the world...

Both concepts are "information" in nature, i.e. knowledge.

You are correct though...one has to jettison the materialist model of the world the approach this issue...

The fact that the materialist model is not working here...is a sign that it is not a good model.

Philip Rand said…
Dr Law

The examples in you piece, I think reflect philosophical confusions concerning "consciousness".

I can liken all your examples with this model.

1/ Pi is a number
2/ Pi is used in trigonometry calculations.
3/ Pi does not correspond to a "point" on a number line.

So, you end up with a philosophical confusion, i.e. Pi is both a number and not a number...

But, if you look at Pi as a relation and not an object then you get somewhere.

If I generalise and assume the diameter of a circle is a dimension and the circumference is an acceleration (circumference is after all a tangent...and a tangent is an acceleration)...then something most interesting happens...

I won't go into the mathematical rigour here...but what you end up is a point on a number line, i.e. Pi=4

This I do think points to the fact that "consciousness" cannot be dealt with as a material thing...in is instead a "relation".

As I have suggested to you previously...reification suffers BIG problems...namely particles don't exist!

Nagel in his latest book comes to the same result...he however does not have the mathematical and physics tools to make his ideas rigorous (and they can be).

Philip Rand said…
So when you write Dr Law:

"But they can never enter my mind and observe what the experience is like for me, from my point of view. "

This is the truth...because your environmental reality is unique...it is unique for all humans because (using a materialist model) the number of "particles" in your local environment is observer dependent (you wrote this in the quote)...so no wonder one cannot know of another's conscious experience exactly.

This is not to say that such an inkling of another's conscious experience is not open to you...because it is...through the mirror neuron portion of the brain...it is just that you are not cognitively aware of this action, i.e. it is hidden from you.

What is interesting are the recent "Rubber hand experiments"...the results I think are quite important philosophically...

For instance, I think they show that Wittgenstein's idea of "knowledge" is correct...

Here, I am thinking of Moore raising his hand and saying "I know this is my hand."

Wittgenstein would say "No, you do not know it is your hand, you are CERTAIN it is your hand."

And that this certainty is not based on cognition...

But, that this certainty may give you wrong knowledge (here we start getting into Private Language issues)...

In many ways, this links directly to your comments concerning Plantenga's take on evolution...because in many ways the results from the Rubber Hand Experiment undermine the idea that True Belief has any role in evolution...sure, it might "look" like that...but Nature has a way of giving us counter-intuitive results...i.e. "irrationality" is adaptive.

Interestingly, I recently heard a driver of the Thrust II rocket car describe the sensations one feels when driving over the speed of sound in a car...

What was particularly interesting is that it seems when one decelerates from the speed of sound to around 500 mph (it only takes 2 seconds)...the sensation of feels is that one is going straight down INTO the ground!!!!!

Again, this is another rubber hand result...so the chap is certain he is going into the ground (i.e. his senses are telling him this)...BUT in reality he is still travelling along the horizontal...very interesting...

Philip Rand said…
Dr Law...

You ended your chapter with:

"In chapter XX “Do We Ever Deserve to be Punished?” I briefly discuss the discovery that the universe is not after all governed by strict and exceptionless laws, but merely by probabilistic laws. So it turns out that the most that someone furnished with full information about my physical body and environment could ever predict about my future behaviour is what I will probably do"

Now, this is plain wrong, wrong, wrong....

Probability is a human information relationship with the universe...it is isn't a real thing...it simply is observational error in a measurement...

This is quite complex...and to a large degree is dependent on what "interpretation" of quantum physics one "believes".

But, since this topic concerns "consciousness"...then I'll give you a valid example of quantum theory using consciousness...

Here, we assume the wave-function itself resides only in the person observing a measurement...let's say it is the path of an electron...here the wave-function DOES NOT describe the actual path (i.e. the real path in the world of the electron)...instead the wave-function is simply a calculation tool for determining the betting odds the observer of the measurement should assign for the outcomes of FUTURE experiments to detect the electron and is no more real than the seat number on your ticket at the Oxford Playhouse...

Think of it like this...say you and I decide to toss a coin, i.e. heads or tails...now this kind of probability is what I have just described, i.e. a future uncertainty...

But, say I toss the coin and record the result...but do it in such a way that I don't let you see the result...

In this latter case, I know the answer and you don't...Now, the probability problem is quite different...it is epistemic uncertainty...in that you don't have enough information about the world to know the result that I know...

So you see, two different kinds of probabilities...and both not about the world...but instead about the relationship of an observer with the world...

I mean, the Schrodinger equation itself is a deterministic equation...i.e. it is an extremely strict task master...

Please, don't bring quantum physics down to the level of Neo-Darwinism :)
Philip Rand said…
Dr Law

I think there exists a big problem with Jackson's thought model.

Namely, I don't think Mary's mind would in fact perceive the colour "red".

Remember, humans are neotenous...and if she has been brought up in a total black and white environment I don't believe her brain would be requesting this "red" colour from the tomato.

I mean, humans have the ability to learn a language (i.e. experience a speaking language, sign language) ...BUT if a child is not taught a language by the time it is 12 or so...it will never learn a language.

It could be similar for colour perception...and in this case the perception would rely entirely on pre-cognitive brain functions, i.e. Familiar memory...one does not "know" one sees red(i.e. ...one as a child is simply taught to see red...no reasons are ever given to the child that the tomato is red...it just is).

It is simply an objective hinge that one trusts.
Edward Ockham said…
I think it's a bandwidth problem. Changing your example slightly. The visual system of brain A is a complex system consisting of a 'big piple' carrying a huge bandwith of data from the retinal surface into the visual cortex. Let's say that knowledge of a colour consists in the hugely complex arrangement of data in the cortex. A person with brain B is trying to gain knowledge of the visual knowledge of the person with brain A. The person with brain B can either get this knowledge directly via the high-bandwidth pipe in their brain. I.e. they could 'see red'. Or they could try to get the knowledge by low bandwidth means, such as reading books, constructing complex theories of vision using mathematics. But that would take too long, and is probably impossible, given that propositional knowledge is stored in a different part of the brain.

So the assumption I challenge is where you say "But Mary previously knew all the physical facts". If knowledge of the physical facts consists in a complex organisation of data in the brain, which needs to be at least as complex as the physical facts themselves, and if it is impossbile to acquire such organisation by low bandwidth methods, then this crucial assumption is false.

"Jackson seems to have shown that there are more facts than just the physical facts." No. There are just the physical facts. But the physical facts in this case are themselves knowledge, i.e. brain states. So knowledge of the physical facts would be knowledge of brain states or knowledge of knowledge. But it is difficult – for purely material reasons – to have a brain state which is itself a complete representation of a brain state.

TT said…
You are correct though...one has to jettison the materialist model of the world the approach this issue...

The fact that the materialist model is not working here...is a sign that it is not a good model.

Why is any of this true?
There are just as many unanswered questions about "physical reality" though I don't necessarily think consciousness is seperate from that.

If you don't know what I mean, define what energy actually is. I mean in what it actually is not vagueries about being able to do work. Energy/mass in the fundamental stuff of the universe and we don't really know what it is at bottom.
We accept all manner of odd properties of matter. There is no ultimate explanation of why any of should be so but we accept it. We privalage consciousness because it is so important to us but why not just accept it as yet one more odd property of matter in certain arrangements.
Philip Rand said…
Well TT...a fairly good definition of energy is that it is a physical attribute of a problem, i.e. energy, momentum, etc.

And that these physical attributes are simply intrinsic information of a real physical measurement.

If one does this then one eventually is lead to the famous equivalence relation:

(Energy)^2=(speed of light)^2*(momentum)^2+(mass)^2*(speed of light)^4

Which simply links mass, momentum and energy.

The thing is this equation defines the extensional co-ordinates of energy and momentum values without any need of a materialist world-view.

At root this is probably the reason that in all Lagrangians in physics equations...they ALL have a squared energy gradient term...and this term defines the intrinsic information of a particular problem...now, information is not a "material" thing.
Philip Rand said…
Oh...remember, if mass is determined by the Higg's...you have to be clear that the Higg's IS NOT a particle...it is more a field (even this is debatable)...but it is definitely not a "material" thing...like a Humean Billiard Ball!

Philip Rand said…
You know Edward Ockham, I think Dr Law would agree with you concerning "knowledge" and "brain-states"...

In his model of evolution knowledge is adaptive...meaning essentially that "knowledge", i.e. something immaterial is a real variable in the universe.

Popular posts from this blog

EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS

(Published in Faith and Philosophy 2011. Volume 28, Issue 2, April 2011. Stephen Law. Pages 129-151) EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS Stephen Law Abstract The vast majority of Biblical historians believe there is evidence sufficient to place Jesus’ existence beyond reasonable doubt. Many believe the New Testament documents alone suffice firmly to establish Jesus as an actual, historical figure. I question these views. In particular, I argue (i) that the three most popular criteria by which various non-miraculous New Testament claims made about Jesus are supposedly corroborated are not sufficient, either singly or jointly, to place his existence beyond reasonable doubt, and (ii) that a prima facie plausible principle concerning how evidence should be assessed – a principle I call the contamination principle – entails that, given the large proportion of uncorroborated miracle claims made about Jesus in the New Testament documents, we should, in the absence of indepen

Why I won't be voting Labour at the next General Election, not even to 'keep the Tories out'.

I have always voted Labour, and have often been a member of the Party, campaigning and canvassing for them. For what it’s worth, here’s my feeling about voting Labour next General Election:   1. When the left vote Labour after they move rightwards, they are encouraged to just move further right, to the point where they are now probably right of where e.g. John Major’s Tory party was. And each time the Tories go further right still. At some point we have got to stop fuelling this toxic drift to the right by making the Labour Party realise that it’s going to start costing them votes. I can’t think of anything politically more important than halting this increasingly frightening rightward slide. So I am no longer voting Labour. 2. If a new socialist party starts up, it could easily hoover up many of the 200k former LP members who have left in disgust (I’d join), and perhaps also pick up union affiliations. They could become the second biggest party by membership quite quickly. Our voting

Aquinas on homosexuality

Thought I would try a bit of a draft out on the blog, for feedback. All comments gratefully received. No doubt I've got at least some details wrong re the Catholic Church's position... AQUINAS AND SEXUAL ETHICS Aquinas’s thinking remains hugely influential within the Catholic Church. In particular, his ideas concerning sexual ethics still heavily shape Church teaching. It is on these ideas that we focus here. In particular, I will look at Aquinas’s justification for morally condemning homosexual acts. When homosexuality is judged to be morally wrong, the justification offered is often that homosexuality is, in some sense, “unnatural”. Aquinas develops a sophisticated version of this sort of argument. The roots of the argument lie in thinking of Aristotle, whom Aquinas believes to be scientifically authoritative. Indeed, one of Aquinas’s over-arching aims was to show how Aristotle’s philosophical system is broadly compatible with Christian thought. I begin with a sketch of Arist