Many Theists (believers in an omniscient, omnipotent, omnibenevolent God) try to make
a 'cumulative case' for the existence of their God. However, what they call a
'cumulative case' is often misleadingly described as such.
A cumulative case can be a
powerful thing. You often find cumulative cases in a court of law. Suppose Jones
is accused of murdering Smith. The prosecution might offer a whole string of
arguments for Jones guilt: Jones' lack of an alibi, Jones' opportunity, Jones'
clear motive, fibres from Jones' clothing otherwise inexplicably found at the crime scene, an eyewitness of Jones committing the murder, Jones' admission of the crime to a cell mate, and so on.
The real strength of such a
cumulative case is this: while any one component argument or piece of evidence
for Jones' guilt might turn out to be no good, what remains can still be more
than sufficient to convict him. Even if the defence can show, for example, that
Jones' admission to his cellmate was faked, the other evidence in combination might still be more
than enough to put Jones behind bars.
But now consider an example
of what some Theists like to call a 'cumulative case' for the existence of God.
- First, they argue that the existence must originate in some sort of necessary being.
- Second, they argue that this necessary being must be omnipotent - must have power without limit.
- Third, they argue that this being must be a person.
- Fourth, they argue the this being must have great intelligence (to account for the design of the universe) - indeed must be omniscient.
- Fifth, they argue that this being must also be omnibenevolent - supremely good.
And so they arrive at the
conclusion that their God - the omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent God
- exists.
An analogy is often drawn by Theists between this sort of supposedly 'cumulative' argument and a climb involving ladders.
The first argument is the first ladder, which gets you a little way up the mountain.
The next ladder gets you a bit higher. Eventually, the last argument provides your
ladder to the summit, and the conclusion that God exists. A 'cumulative case' is
built, raising us step by step from valley to summit.
But is this sort of argument
for theism really a cumulative case, and, most importantly, does it have the characteristic
strength of a cumulative case?
Theists will often say about
such a 'cumulative case' that even if the last step of the argument is
suspect, that doesn't matter too much. Perhaps their ladders don't then take
them all the way to the summit. But
at least the ladders get them very close. Close enough for it to take just a
modest leap of faith to put them on top.
In my opinion, this sort of 'cumulative
case' argument is probably best not thought of as a cumulative case at all. It certainly
lacks the sort of strength that we have seen is often exhibited by true cumulative
cases made in a court of law.
Consider an analogy.
Suppose Johnson has been
killed. The accused - let's call him
McLatchie - stands in the dock, and the prosecution make their case against
him. They argue like so:
First, they argue that
someone killed Johnson.
Then they argue that this
someone was a human.
Then they argue this human
had two legs.
Then they argue that the killer spoke English.
Then they argue that the killer wore clothes.
Finally, they argue that this
English-speaking, two-legged, clothes-wearing human is indeed McLatchie.
Now that is indeed a 'cumulative
case' in our Theist's 'ladder' sense. We again climb up a ladder, arriving
first at one conclusion, then working our way up to the next, until finally we
reach the summit and the conclusion that McLatchie is guilty.
Now suppose McLatchie's defence team were
to try the following move. The say, "But hang on, your final argument - that
it's McLatchie that's guilty - is very shaky." In response, the prosecution say:
"Well, remember we are climbing a
ladder here. Our case for McLatchie's guilt builds and builds! And most of our
arguments are really good (that the killer is a human, had two legs etc.) - you
can't deny that!
So even if the last bit of our case is wobbly, still the cumulative
case for McLatchie's guilt remains strong! You must at least admit we've at
least got pretty close to convicting
McLatchie."
The truth, of course, is that the prosecution
have got nowhere near finding
McLatchie guilty.
We noted earlier that an
attractive feature of cumulative cases is this - even if one bit of the case fails,
the various other bits can still be sufficient to establish your conclusion.
But notice this feature is missing in the case for
McLatchie's guilt.
So far as McLatchie being the
guilty person, almost everything hangs on that one last argument.
All the defence need to do,
to get McLatchie justifiably acquitted, is establish reasonable doubt about just
that one last argument.
But then isn't the same true
of our Theist's 'cumulative' case' for the existence of their God?
Again - almost everything
hangs on that last bit of their argument - the argument for God's goodness - widely considered the most suspect bit! If that last step fails,
their case for their sort of Theism collapses, in just the same way
that, if that final step in the prosecution's case fails, the case for
McLatchie being the murderer collapses.
That's a very poor sort of 'cumulative
case'.
Most importantly, if any one
component argument of a true cumulative case argument fails, the entire case doesn't necessarily collapse. No
component need be singly necessary. The failure of any one component can
usually be compensated for by the safety net provided by the other components.
That, as I say, is an
advantage of typical cumulative case arguments.
But as should now be clear,
that's NOT what we have when it comes to the cases for Theism and McLatchie's guilt. Here, one component of the argument
is absolutely essential. If it fails, the case collapses.
Note there are many
people who might be guilty of the murder
of which McLatchie is accused, even if all the other arguments making up the
'cumulative case' for McLatchie's guilt, bar the last, are sound. We're not
close to finding McLatchie guilty yet.
But then there are many omnipotent and omniscient gods that might account for the existence, fine-tuned character, and so on of the universe. Including e.g. an evil God, belief in which we all still rightly consider absurd, not withstanding that the exact same sort of cumulative case can be made for him (differing only in that final step). Are we then close to establishing the existence of an evil God? Of course not.
But then there are many omnipotent and omniscient gods that might account for the existence, fine-tuned character, and so on of the universe. Including e.g. an evil God, belief in which we all still rightly consider absurd, not withstanding that the exact same sort of cumulative case can be made for him (differing only in that final step). Are we then close to establishing the existence of an evil God? Of course not.
So, it seems to me that if there's no good
argument for God's goodness, we're not even close to establishing that the Judeo
Christian God exists.
Image source here: (it's a video) https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xfMbylfKP2c
Image source here: (it's a video) https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xfMbylfKP2c
Comments
Whereas in the theistic 'cumulative' case, it's the sequence of arguments, and their dependency on each preceding argument, that in totality (and only in totality) leads to conviction. In this sense, I can't see that it's even proper to call it a cumulative argument. A better term would be a progressive argument?
Another nitpick would be that in your examples, in the legal case what's presented is an accumulation of objective evidence, where as in the theistic case what you're presented with is a dependent sequence of arguments. In that sense, these are not qualitively similar presentations at all.
In short then, in one you have dependency and the other, you do not.
My admiration and respect for you as an intellectual and philosopher can not be too overstated. You have a gift for, and I'll use the technical term her in the US, 'pooh-poohing' things. Oxford Dictionary states cumulative is "Increasing or increased in quantity, degree, or force by successive additions." A classical theistic case for God is no more or no less a cumulative case. Omnipotence is based on the idea of a Creator must be SO powerful to create a Universe. The other Omni's follow the case, as it is made.
I'm sorry, but this clearly is a case where you are negating a very legitimate way to 'prove' the existence of God (and His attributes).
It's true that the chain of stipulations can just as easily end with an omnimalevolent God as an omnibenevolent one, but that seems less significant than the fact that it is a chain of stipulations, no more than that.
1. A being create the universe
2. He has to be omnipotent because he created the universe.
3. Is really just nonsense.
4. Since he created the universe he must be all intelligent
5. Since he is all powerful, all intelligent, and created the universe, he must therefore be good.
Therefore god exists.
At the time, gods were pervasive, well, the belief in them. They all had roles and functions within society, but monotheism deviated and required that the being be elevated to all-powerful, because there are times that god actually fails (Judges 1:19, god fails because the coastal people had iron chariots, but by Judges 4, he figures out how to defeat iron chariots). It's more god starts out as a local deity and the omni-everything is added later and rationalized.