Forthcoming in Religious Studies. (Image Flickr creative commons, by Marcel Dzama)
The
X-claim argument against religious belief
Introduction
This paper outlines an argument against religious
belief: the X-claim argument. The
argument is novel at least in the sense that it has not yet been clearly
articulated or addressed before in the philosophical literature. However, the
argument is closely related to two more familiar varieties of argument
currently receiving philosophical attention, namely: (i) arguments from
religious diversity, and (ii) naturalistic debunking arguments (e.g. Freudian,
Marxist, and evolutionary). I set out the X-claim argument, show that it has
some prima facie plausibility, distinguish it from these other two arguments
with which it might easily be confused, and, finally, explain why it has some
significant advantages over these more familiar arguments against religious
belief.
PART
ONE: THE X-CLAIM ARGUMENT AGAINST RELIGIOUS BELIEF
1.
X-claims
Humans have a
well-established capacity for generating false but nevertheless rich and
seductive systems of belief. One variety of false belief to which we are
particularly prone – and in which psychologists are taking an increasing interest
– is belief in extraordinary hidden agency: beings, acting on the
basis of beliefs and desires, that are not visible to the naked eye in the way
human beings usually are. Belief in the existence of such agents is ubiquitous,
as Steven Pinker notes:
In all human cultures, people believe
that the soul lives on after death, that ritual can change the physical world
and divine the truth, and that illness and misfortune are caused and alleviated
by a variety of invisible person-like entities: spirits, ghosts, saints, evils,
demons, cherubim or Jesus, devils and gods.
All cultures, you might ask? Yes, all
cultures. I give you an example of a culture we're well familiar with, that of
the contemporary United States. The last time I checked the figures, 25% of
Americans believe in witches, 50% in ghosts, 50% in the devil, 50% believe that
the Book of Genesis is literally true, 69% believe in angels, 87% believe Jesus
was raised from the dead, and 96% believe in a god or a universal spirit.
(Pinker 2004)
Humans often invoke hidden
agency to account for what they cannot otherwise explain. When we could not explain
why the planets moved in the way they do, we supposed they must be, or be
controlled by, gods. When we could not otherwise explain natural diseases and
disasters, we believed them to be the work of malevolent beings, such as
witches and demons. When we couldn’t explain why the seasons rolled by, or why
plants sprang back to life in the spring, we supposed that these events must be
under the control of other hidden agents. As a result of this tendency to reach
for extraordinary hidden agency, particularly when presented with a mystery, we
have hypothesized countless hidden beings and developed rich and complex
narratives about them.
Belief in extraordinary hidden
agency is often accompanied by a belief in super-powers and super-faculties. The
hidden agents are themselves typically supposed to possess certain
extraordinary powers and faculties. In addition, our own ability to detect the
presence of such agents is often explained by our possessing such faculties. Mediums
claim the uncanny ability to experience and communicate with the dead. Some suppose
they encounter or communicate with other kinds of hidden being, including
demons and gods (the Delphic oracle, for example). More recently, our ability
to detect hidden agents is believed to have been technologically enhanced: consider
EVP, in which spirit voices can supposedly be heard in radio static. Belief
systems involving such hidden agents also often include beliefs in
extraordinary or magically-imbued objects – such as lucky charms, totems, and holy
relics – and/or extraordinary or magical events – including planetary
alignments, religious miracles, moments of divine creation.
Such beliefs are not
restricted to the unintelligent or uneducated. A Gallup poll conducted in 2001
suggested U.S. college students are at least as likely to believe in ghosts as
the general population (40% to 39%).[1] Even some of the most outlandish X-claim belief systems can boast
sophisticated devotees. Sir Arthur Conan Doyle –creator of that
quintessentially rational character Sherlock Holmes – believed in fairies and
was successfully hoaxed by two little girls armed with paper cutouts and a film
camera. In the U.S., Young Earth Creationism (the view that the Judeo-Christian
God exists and created the universe and all living ‘kinds’ in just six days
sometime in the 10,000 years) is defended by PhDs holding tenured university
positions.
Those who believe in
such hidden beings usually consider their belief reasonable. Often, belief is
justified by an appeal to testimony.
Believers refer to reports of individuals (mediums, gurus, etc.) claiming
either to have some form of direct knowledge of the hidden agents themselves,
or at least to have witnessed extraordinary events involving them. Belief in
such agency is also often rooted in certain kinds of subjective experience. Believers may report a powerful sense that
they are themselves directly subjectively aware of, and perhaps receiving
communications or revelations from, some kind of otherwise invisible being, be
it a deceased relative, a nature spirit, an angel, or a god. Typically, this
direct and immediate access is supposed to be rooted not in ordinary sense
perception but in some additional sense such as a god- or spirit-sense.
Henceforth, by 'subjective experiences' I'll mean experiences of this supposed
sort.
Sometimes, such appeals to testimony and subjective
experience are supplemented by some supposedly 'hard' evidence (a photograph of
a fairy, for example, or a miracle scientifically authenticated by the Congregatio
de Causis Sanctorum).
By X-claims I shall mean claims about such hidden beings - agents, who act on the basis of
beliefs and desires, but who aren't usually visible to the naked eye in the way
that human beings, cats, dogs, etc., are -
and associated magical and/or extraordinary powers, faculties, objects and
events[2].
X-claims are claims with which we humans are peculiarly fascinated. They are
also claims about which we have proven to be highly unreliable judges of truth.
Around the world and throughout history we find communities believing, on the
basis of testimony and subjective experience, X-claims that we can be
justifiably confident are false. We suppose, rightly, that those who believed
in the gods of ancient Egypt, Greece, and Rome were mistaken. Many within the
‘skeptic’ community believe, justifiably, that TV’s Psychic Sally doesn't
really communicate with the dead, and that Conan Doyle’s beliefs in
spiritualism and the Cottingley fairies were mistaken.
Part of the
case for supposing we're unreliable judges of the truth regarding X-claims is
provided by X-claim diversity. Some
beliefs involving such hidden agents are incompatible with others. Religious
belief provides one obvious example – religions disagree about the number of
gods, the characteristics of those gods, and so on. Only a minority of these
conflicting god claims can be true.
However, X-claim diversity is just one
facet of a much broader range of evidence supporting the view that we are
generally unreliable judges of their truth, particularly when judgement is
grounded in some combination of testimony and subjective experience. Many
X-claims have been straightforwardly falsified. Each year, a variety of such
claims, even when they might initially have seemed well supported, are
successfully debunked in the pages of Skeptical
Inquirer magazine. A significant proportion has been shown to have
resulted, or likely resulted, from fraud, from the misidentification of natural
phenomena, and so on. Here are a few of my favourite examples (drawn from
countless others): the Cottingham fairy photographs were almost certainly forged
using paper cutouts by the two young girls - there were no fairies[3];
a sneezing spirit-being supposedly witnessed and recorded by the Haunted Homes TV programme turned out to
be an automatic air-freshener (though that detail was not broadcast)[4];
and the Flatwoods Monster (a man-like figure with red face and pointed hood who
hissed and glided toward the group shortly after UFOs were spotted) was almost
certainly a barn owl.[5]
In none of these cases was any sort of extraordinary hidden agency actually witnessed.
Our tendency to systematically over-detect agency is in part due to a
phenomenon known as pareidolia, where
the mind perceives a familiar pattern where none actually exists. For example,
we are particularly prone to see faces where none exist (in clouds, in the
embers of a fire, etc.) and to hear voices in random sounds. More generally,
psychologists have noted our 'readiness to attribute intentionality to objects
on the basis of minimal cues' (French and Stone (2013), 197).
Note that what evidence we have for
our unreliability regarding X-claims is for a proneness toward false positive belief in X-claims. We know,
regarding our belief in such hidden agents and associated magical and/or
extraordinary powers, faculties, objects and events, that a very large
proportion of these beliefs are mistaken. By contrast, there’s little evidence
to suggest we're prone to false negative
X-claim beliefs - i.e. that we're highly susceptible to mistakenly disbelieving
in hidden beings etc. that actually are
there.[6]
Struck by this peculiar proneness to
false positive beliefs across the range of X-claims, those working in the
cognitive science of religion have posited a mechanism to account for it: an
evolved Hyperactive Agency Detecting Device
(HADD) (Barrett 2004, Clark and
Barrett 2010). Scientists have suggested that we have evolved to over-detect
agency because, while over-detection of agency is not particularly costly to us
in terms of survival and reproduction in our ancestral environment, a failure
to detect agents that are there can be very costly indeed. A sabre-toothed
tiger missed, for example, is likely to remove you from the gene pool. This
constitutional tendency to over-detect agency explains why, for example, when
you hear a rustle in the bushes as you walk home alone in the dark, your first
instinctive reaction is to think 'There's someone there!' The evolution of an
HADD may account for a tendency to believe an agent is present even when none
can be clearly observed, resulting in belief in ghosts and spirits, for
example.
Of course, none of this is to say that no X-claim is
true, or that no one can ever reasonably believe an X-claim. Perhaps the
fairies will finally conclusively reveal themselves, demonstrating their magic
to scientific experts and appearing on daytime TV. Even if the agents remain
hidden, evidence sufficient to establish their existence beyond reasonable
doubt might be revealed. Perhaps scientific investigation will establish
conclusively that some people really can communicate with the deceased.
However, X-claims aren't usually accompanied by evidence of such strength.
Typically, they are justified by appeal to testimony and/or subjective
experiences of the sort outlined above.
2. Sylvia and the dead
Consider the following
hypothetical, but I suggest typical, example of someone strongly committed to a
system of belief built around X-claims. Sylvia has a strong subjective
impression that the dead walk among us. She is sometimes overcome by a powerful
sense that the dead are present and making themselves known to her. Sylvia has
thoughts that seem to her to be communications or revelations from the
deceased. Sylvia believes these thoughts often provide helpful guidance. In
addition, Sylvia has investigated and finds compelling the testimony of others
(friends, relations, the authors of books she has read, etc.) concerning
ghosts, spirits, and communications from beyond the grave, including dramatic
tales of disasters averted as a result of people receiving such messages.
Suppose Sylvia is now
presented with the evidence I have outlined above: evidence that we humans are
highly prone to false positive beliefs in X-claims when those beliefs are
grounded in a combination of testimony and subjective experience. This evidence
is new to Sylvia. How should she respond?
3. Knowledge defeat
Readers familiar with
the literature on epistemic defeat may anticipate an argument turning on the
thought that Sylvia has just come to possess a defeater for her X-claim beliefs, and that consequently she can no
longer be said to know that the dead walk among us. Defeat cases involves a
belief losing some epistemic status - typically including knowledge - in
circumstances of a certain kind.
Here's a familiar
putative example. Suppose I observe that the widgets on an assembly line look
red, and so come to believe they are red. I'm then told by an authority I know
to be generally reliable and trustworthy that the widgets are lit by a red
light that makes even non-red things look red. On considering this case, many
intuit that on acquiring this new evidence I come to possess an undermining
defeater for my original belief. They suppose that, as a consequence of my
coming to possess this new evidence, that I can no longer be said to know the widgets are red.
Here's a second example.
Suppose I seem to see a snake on the ground in front of me, and so come to
believe there's a snake there. Then a reliable and trustworthy authority tells
me that I have been given a drug that produces super-realistic visual
snake-hallucinations. Again, many have the intuition that, given this new
evidence, I can no longer be said to know there's a snake there.
In both the above cases
I come to possess new evidence that the method by which I formed my original
belief is, in the circumstances in which I formed it, not to be trusted. And
this, it's widely supposed, is sufficient to undermine knowledge.
The above intuitions
about defeat might now be deployed in an argument for the conclusion that, on
being presented with the evidence that we humans are highly prone to false
positive X-claim beliefs when those beliefs are grounded in some combination of
testimony and subjective experience, Sylvia can no longer be said to know the
dead walk among us. For she, too, comes to possess evidence that the method by
which she formed her X-claim beliefs is not to be trusted.
4. Rationality defeat
I will avoid framing my
argument in terms of knowledge
defeat. I think the jury is out on whether knowledge is lost in such cases. Maria Lasonen Aarnio (2010) suggests the
intuition that knowledge must be lost in such cases is misleading. She argues
that externalists should take seriously the suggestion that knowledge can be
retained even in the face of seemingly strong defeating evidence.
Suppose, for example, that I just stick
with my belief that the widgets are red even after having been given good
evidence that they are lit by a red light that makes them look red even when
they're not. But suppose that evidence is misleading: there is no red light,
and the widgets are indeed red. Then, suggests Lasonen Aarnio, I may still know the widgets are red. For it may be
that the relevant externalist conditions on knowledge are satisfied (so, for
example, the method by which I arrive at my belief may still be reliable or safe[7]). So why do so many of us
have the intuition that knowledge is lost in such cases? Lasonen Aarnio
suggests that what misleads us is the fact that it is, in a certain sense, unreasonable for believers to continue
to believe under such circumstances. Lasonen Aarnio says 'subjects
who retain belief in defeat cases act in an epistemically unreasonable manner.'
(2010, 12)
In what sense
unreasonable? Consider, for example, the rule or method of belief formation
that tells you to believe that p when you see that p even in
the presence of good evidence for thinking that your senses are not to be
trusted. This method is, in a sense, good, in that if you follows it, beliefs
obtained as a result will be safe (given you can see that p only if p is true, this
policy cannot produce a false belief).
However, the
above method is epistemically a bad method to adopt, suggests Lasonen Aarnio,
because adopting it results in a bad
disposition. Lasonen Aarnio notes that a 'subject
who adopts this method is also disposed to believe p when she merely seems to see that p in the
presence of evidence for thinking that her senses are not to be trusted' (2010,
14 my italics). But then, were a subject to adopt the method, they would end up
believing p in a significant
proportion of cases in which the evidence that their senses are not to be
trusted is not misleading. So while
the method is indeed safe, its adoption results in dispositions that are not
knowledge conducive:
This
is why the rule believe p when you see that p in the presence of evidence
for thinking that your senses are not to be trusted is not part of a policy
that is knowledge conducive in the intended sense. A reasonable subject would
not adopt or follow such a rule, even though it is success entailing. (2010,
15)
Regarding subjects who adopt the method of dogmatically adhering to
previous beliefs in the face of non-misleading new evidence that their senses
are not to be trusted, Lasonen Aarnio says:
it
will seem to them as if they are following the same method as in good cases, thereby
retaining knowledge, whereas they will in reality be retaining beliefs in
falsehoods. Overall, it would be much better to follow a policy recommending
the revision of belief in the light of new evidence. This is why reasonable
subjects adjust their beliefs in defeat cases. (2010, 15)
Someone who is presented
with evidence that the method by which they acquired their original belief is
untrustworthy should withhold belief. If they fail to do so, they are being (in
Lasonen Aarnio's sense) unreasonable, and can be properly criticised for
sticking with their original belief. But that's not to say they are not
employing a reliable or safe method, or indeed that they don't know. The reason why many of us intuit that
knowledge is lost in such cases, suggests Lasonen Aarnio, is that we assume
that if a belief is unreasonable then it can't constitute knowledge. Lasonen
Aarnio questions that assumption.
Let's now return to the
case of Sylvia. I shan't argue that, given the new evidence available to her,
Sylvia can't be said to know the dead walk among us. Perhaps, for the reasons
Lasonen Aarnio suggests, Sylvia does still know (if she really is aware of the
presence of the deceased by virtue of some sort of safe method, say). However,
if Lasonen Aarnio is correct, then if Sylvia continues to believe on the same
basis, she no longer believes reasonably.
If Sylvia sticks to her guns and continues to believe, she can be properly
criticised for doing so.
Perhaps we can still
talk about a form of defeat in such cases, however. For if Lasonen Aarnio is
correct, it remains true to say that some positive epistemic status is lost.
Only what is lost is, if not knowledge, then at least reasonable belief. So
let's say that in such cases we come to possess, if not a knowledge defeater,
then at least a rationality defeater.
When I acquire evidence that forming snake beliefs on the basis of their visual
appearance is a method that, in my drugged state, is untrustworthy, I come to
possess a rationality defeater for my original belief. But then it appears that
so, too, does Sylvia after she acquires evidence that forming X-claim beliefs
on the basis of testimony and subjective experience is an untrustworthy method.
5. On individuating methods
According to externalists,
in determining whether Sylvia knows,
we should be individuating methods externalistically. True, the methods
employed by Sylvia and other X-claim believers might, from the point of view of
the various subjects involved, seem very similar. However, it may be that,
unlike other X-claim believers also relying on a subjective sense of presence,
Sylvia is employing a method that actually is safe. She really does possess a
reliably-functioning spirit sense. But then, assuming an externalist account on
which, say, knowledge is true belief delivered by such a safe method, Sylvia can
still know her X-claim belief is true. When it comes to assessing whether
Sylvia knows, we shouldn't count Sylvia as employing the 'same method' as other
X-claim believers who happen to believe on the basis of subjectively similar
experiences.
However note that, even
if, when it comes to determining whether Sylvia knows the dead walk among us, we should be individuating methods
externalistically, that's not to say that Sylvia's continued X-claim beliefs
remain reasonable once she comes to
possess the (in fact misleading) evidence that the method by which she acquired
her beliefs is untrustworthy. Sylvia's continued X-claim beliefs are
unreasonable in Lasonen Aarnio's sense because, as a consequence of her
adopting a policy of continuing to believe even when presented with evidence
that her method of arriving at belief is untrustworthy, Sylvia manifests a
disposition that is not knowledge conducive.
6. The X-claim argument against religious belief
Religions are typically built
around X-claims. They usually posit hidden agents – a god or gods – with
extraordinary or miraculous faculties and powers (some forms of Buddhism being
a notable exception). Associated with these super-beings are extraordinary and
miraculous objects and events – miraculous healings, holy places, relics, and
so on. Religions also typically involve the thought that some or all of us
possess some sort of super-faculty by which we may come to possess knowledge of
these beings.
Mainstream Christianity
is an obvious example of a religion in which X-claims play a major role.
Mainstream Christians believe in an invisible agent – the Judeo-Christian God –
possessing both the super-power of omnipotence and the super-faculty of
omniscience. They also believe in associated extraordinary and miraculous
events, including the pivotal miracle of the resurrection. For most Christians,
these X-claims lie at the heart of their faith. Some add further X-claims to
this doctrinal core, such as claims about holy relics (the Turin shroud, say)
or the ongoing miraculous activities of saints.
Most religious people –
including most Christians – suppose they hold their religious beliefs
reasonably, or at least not unreasonably. Many hold their belief primarily on
the basis of testimony and/or subjective experience. Consider a hypothetical
Christian, Peter, who supports his core Christian X-claim beliefs by pointing
to testimony in the form of scripture and reports of miracles ancient and
modern. In addition, Peter supposes he has direct awareness of God and the
truth of various central Christian X-claims, an awareness he believes is
afforded him by a sensus divinitatis
and the activity of the Holy Spirit.
But if Sylvia should be
skeptical about her X-claims once she acquires evidence of the
untrustworthiness of the method by which she acquired them, shouldn’t Peter
similarly be skeptical about his religious X-claims once he learns of
untrustworthiness of that same method? After all, like Sylvia, Peter considers
his beliefs justified by virtue of testimony and his own subjective
experiences. But the evidence reveals this is precisely the sort of situation
in which we are highly prone to false positive belief in X-claims. If this
evidence should lead Sylvia to withhold from believing her X-claims, shouldn’t
it also lead Peter to withhold from believing? If it's unreasonable for Sylvia
to continue to believe after coming to possess this new evidence, surely it is
no less unreasonable for Peter to continue to believe.
Note that Peter might
suppose, correctly, that, unlike most X-claim believers, he really is employing
a safe method of acquiring beliefs, a method that is in fact delivering
knowledge. Nevertheless, Peter believes unreasonably, in Laasonen Arnio's
sense, if he possesses the (in fact misleading) information that the method by
which he acquired his beliefs is unreliable and not to be trusted. Under such
circumstances, Peter shouldn't believe, even if, as a matter of fact, he's
right in supposing he knows.
Admittedly, there are
forms of religion in which X-claims play little if any role. Consider an
anti-realist version of Christianity on which the claims that God exists and
miracles happen are not understood as being literally true, or a redacted
version in which all reference to God, miracles and an afterlife are removed
leaving only edifying tales and moral teaching (along the lines of Thomas
Jefferson’s The Life and
Morals of Jesus of Nazareth). The X-claim argument constitutes no a threat to religious beliefs of
that sort.
However, for many
religions, including the mainstream monotheistic religions as understood by the
vast majority of their followers, X-claims form an essential part of their core
doctrine. And for any religion in which X-claims form an essential part of core
doctrine, where those X-claims are grounded largely in testimony and subjective
experiences of the sort outlined above, the X-claim argument appears to pose a
significant threat to reasonable belief.
My aim here has been to
sketch out in broad terms the X-claim argument against religion in such a way
that it might be seen to have at least some prima facie plausibility. Let S&T
be a combination of testimony and/or subjective experiences of a certain
sort (a subjective sense of presence of, and/or revelation/communication from,
some hidden agency, apparently delivered other than by the usual perceptual
routes). Then one way of summarizing the X-claim argument is like so:
(1) We are highly prone to false positive
X-claim beliefs when our beliefs are grounded in just S&T.
(2) Learning (1) supplies a subject with
a rationality defeater for any positive X-claim belief of theirs grounded in
just S&T.
(3) S’s religious positive X-claim
beliefs are grounded in just S&T.
(4) Learning (1) supplies S with a
rationality defeater for their religious positive X-claim beliefs.
The above argument would appear to apply
to many religious folk (and of course also to others who believe e.g., that the
dead walk among us, etc.). Their religious positive X-claim beliefs are
grounded in just S&T. But then, given (2), their learning (1) supplies them
with a rationality defeater for their religious X-claim beliefs. In which case,
on learning (1), they should cease holding those religious beliefs, and can be
properly criticised for not doing so. I have suggested the above argument has a
good deal of prima facie plausibility. Premise (1) is surely true. I consider
premise (2) highly plausible.
I now anticipate six responses to the
above argument.
First, believers may insist that, even if
(2) is true, that’s not yet to say their religious positive X-claim belief
grounded in just S&T faces a rationality defeater. It's usually
acknowledged by those who frame these kinds of objection within the vocabulary
of ‘defeat’ that defeaters can be defeated. If I acquire evidence that the
widgets before me that look red are illuminated by a red light that makes
non-red things look red, then that surely supplies me with a rationality
defeater for my perceptually grounded belief that the widgets are red. But if
then I acquire further evidence that I'm viewing the widgets through a filter
that corrects the colour appearance of things illuminated by that red light,
then my rationality defeater faces rational defeat. Similarly, while learning
(1) might generate a rationality defeater for my religious X-claim beliefs
grounded in just S&T, I might nevertheless possess evidence defeating that
defeater. I might possess evidence of some further feature F of my situation
such that, while positive X-claim beliefs grounded in just S&T are usually
false, that's not the case when this further feature F is present.
What might this further feature F be?
What might, say, a Christian whose religious belief is grounded solely in
S&T say about the peculiarities of their own situation that would allow
them reasonably to suppose they possess a defeater for the rationality defeater
that (1) might otherwise appear to supply?
I won’t explore this issue further here
other than to say that I suspect the prospects of a religious person being able
to say something reasonable along these lines are fairly dim. In particular,
note that to possess a defeater for the above rationality defeater, they will
need good evidence that their situation involves some feature F that, when
present, has the consequence that positive X-claim beliefs based on S&T are
usually true. It won't do for the religious person to defend the rationality of
their continued belief by just insisting without evidence that their situation
differs from that of other X-claim believers in that, unlike those other
believers, they really do employ a method that's safe. For even if what they
insist is true, that won't rescue their belief from the charge of irrationality
given this same policy of dogmatic insistence, when employed by other X-claim
believers, will result in widespread false belief. That's still a policy that's
unreasonable, in Lasonen Aarnio's sense, for it results in a disposition that
is not knowledge conducive.
Second, critics may point out that my
argument won’t apply to, say, the members of isolated religious communities
largely unaware of (1). The X-claim argument is a threat only so far as the
religious beliefs of those aware of (1) are concerned. True. But then surely
any reasonably well-informed contemporary Westerner is likely to be aware of
(1).
Third, the X-claim argument is not a
threat to religious belief systems of which X-claims do not form an essential
part. For then the X-claims might be dropped while the belief system is
retained. However, typically, mainstream believers of mainstream religions
consider a number of X-claims to be essential to their religion. For example, most
Christians consider belief in the resurrection essential to their faith. The
X-claim argument constitutes a threat to Christianity as that majority
understand it.
Fourth,
(1) might be challenged on the grounds that by an 'X-claim' I really just mean
a claim concerning something 'spooky', i.e. concerning the existence of
something that, by the scientific standards of the time, counts as mysterious
or hard to account for naturalistically. But then it's by no means obvious that
the majority of such 'X-claims' are false. Consider, for example, the
surprising claim that two spatially isolated objects (i.e. two electrons in
locations sufficiently far apart that information would need to travel faster
than the speed of light to get from one to another) can be such that a change
in one affects a change in the other. When this prediction was made, the best
physics of the day struggled to account for its truth. Indeed, its truth
appeared to require the operation of what Einstein called 'spooky action at a
distance'. But then wasn't this 'spooky' prediction an X-claim, an X-claim now
widely considered true? Science provide numerous other examples of beliefs that
are, or were, X-claims, and that are, or are very probably, true. So it is not
obvious that a majority of X-claim beliefs are false.
The above objection is based on
misunderstanding. To begin with, note that, as I define X-claims, they are
claims specifically about hidden agents. The above prediction concerning
quantum entanglement involved no such agents, merely something Einstein found
'spooky'. That we're highly prone to false belief in 'spooky' things is a vague
and easily contestable claim. That we're highly prone to false positive beliefs
in invisible agents is a well-established and far more precisely articulated
fact for which scientists are now developing a range of scientific
explanations. Further,
note that prediction about quantum entanglement, even if it did constitute and
X-claim (which it doesn't), is in any case not grounded in S&T.
The X-claim argument requires only that we be prone to false positive X-claim
beliefs when they are grounded in
S&T, not that we be prone to false positive X-claim beliefs when grounded in
some other way, e.g. experimentally.
The fifth objection is that the X-claim
argument doesn't threaten religious
X-claim beliefs grounded in something other than S&T. So for example,
for someone who accepts theism on the basis of a philosophical argument, the
X-claim argument does not, as it stands, generate a rationality defeater.
However, notice that the core doctrines of religious belief systems usually
extend far beyond what philosophical and non-testimony-dependent scientific
argument are thought, even by the faithful, to support. That Jesus was raised
from the dead, for example, is a Christian X-claim belief that even the
Christian will presumably acknowledge is grounded in S&T. The resurrection
doesn’t appear to be the sort of thing that could be established by means of
armchair, philosophical reflection, for example. But then, even if theism can
be shown to be invulnerable to the X-claim argument (given some sound
philosophical argument for theism), Christianity, in so far as it requires the
resurrection, still faces a rationality defeater. Moreover, note that the
X-claim argument, if cogent, pulls away the safety net that an appeal to
subjective experience might otherwise seem to have offered theists should their
philosophical and scientific argument for theism turn out not to be cogent. The
X-claim argument, if sound, makes the rationality of theism turn crucially on
the success of such arguments.
Here's
the sixth objection. Surely, the X-claim argument establishes at best that, in
so far as the beliefs are grounded in some combination of S&T, we should be
sceptical about the beliefs that angels, ghosts, fairies, demons, spirit
guides, ancestors, gods, and so on exist, but not whether extraordinary invisible agents exist. For perhaps, on
most of the occasions on which we take ourselves to be experiencing some sort
of extraordinary hidden agency, we really are experiencing such agency - it's
just the way in which we categorise
that agency that's mistaken. Our cultural expectations etc. misleadingly colour
what we experience, leading us to suppose we're experiencing ghosts, fairies,
demons, spirit guides, ancestors, gods, and so on, when in truth none of these
things exist, though the extraordinary hidden agents do. But then the fact that
we know we're highly unreliable judges of whether angels, ghosts, fairies,
spirit guides, gods, are present should not lead us to conclude we are
unreliable judges of whether hidden agency is present, and so should not lead
us to be sceptical about the existence of such hidden agency per se, even if scepticism regarding the
particular ways in which we characterise that agency is warranted.[8]
I'll
make three comments in this response to this sixth objection.
First,
once we know we know that, when it comes to extraordinary hidden agency, we're
highly unreliable judges of what such
agency is like, that can (in at least some circumstances) suffice to raise justified
doubts about our ability to judge whether there's any agency there at all. Suppose
Ted, Bert, Sarah, and Alice enter a room in turn and report back what they
observe. Ted reports he saw just a twenty foot giant in the room, Bert just a
two inch high fairy, Sarah just a full-size lion, and Alice just a small flying
bird. Their diversity of opinion won't just lead us to doubt whether there's a
giant, fairy, lion, or bird in the room; we'll also be justifiably sceptical
about whether there's any agent in the room at all. Scepticism about even the existence
of agency appears justified when there's not just disagreement, but very dramatic disagreement, about its character, as
in the above case. But isn't dramatic disagreement just what we're presented
with when we turn to belief in X-claims about fairies, ghosts, spirits, gods, angels,
demons, and so on?
Second,
the above objection overlooks the fact that what evidence we have concerning
the unreliability of our judgements about extraordinary hidden agency extends
well beyond mere diversity of opinion
about what such agency is like. Let's suppose, for the sake of argument, that widespread
disagreement establishes only that we're unreliable judges of what such agency
is like, not whether it's there. Still, there remains considerable other evidence that we are highly prone
to judging such agency is present when it's not. We have a well-documented
tendency to over attribute agency on the basis of minimal cues (French and
Stone (2013), 197). There is, for example, our well-established tendency to
think agency is present when it's not due to e.g. pareidolia - the tendency to
see faces, hear voices, and so on where there are none. As we noted earlier, there's
also much compelling evidence of the falsehood of a large proportion of our S&T-grounded
beliefs in the even the presence of
such extraordinary hidden agency. See the previously discussed examples of the
Cottingley fairies, the Flatwoods monster, and the sneezing ghost of Haunted Homes. There weren't real,
extraordinary hidden agents that the young Cottingley girls mistook for fairies; rather, there were no
such agents at all - just paper cut
outs. There wasn't an extraordinary being from The Beyond wandering Flatwoods,
just a barn owl. There wasn't an extraordinary hidden agent that was mistakenly categorised as a ghost in
that Haunted Homes episode; rather, there
was no extraordinary agent at all - just an air-freshener. And so on.
Thirdly,
even if it were true (which it isn't) that we're justified in being skeptical only
about our categorisation of such hidden agency, not belief in its existence,
even such limited scepticism will in any case spell doom for much religious
belief. For, in so far as religious belief does involve belief in such
extraordinary hidden agency, it tends essentially to involve specific
categorisations of it (as e.g. an extraordinary hidden agency worthy of our worship, deserving our gratitude, as and so on).
I'll finish with a more general comment
about the above objections. Note that, even if we were to deny (2), insisting
that learning (1) fails to provide a full rationality defeater for any X-claim
belief grounded in S&T, it may be that learning (1) should at least lead
those whose X-claim belief are grounded in just S&T to hold those beliefs
less firmly, perhaps much less firmly. In which case the X-claim argument might
still contribute, perhaps significantly, towards a cumulative case for skepticism regarding religious X-claim beliefs
grounded in S&T.
PART TWO: CONTRAST WITH THE ARGUMENT FROM RELIGIOUS DIVERSITY AND
NATURALISTIC DEBUNKING ARGUMENTS
The X-claim argument is
related to, but distinct from, two other popular arguments against religious
belief, arguments currently receiving philosophical attention: arguments from
religious diversity and naturalistic debunking arguments. As we shall see, the
X-claim argument has the advantage of sidestepping certain stock objections to
those other arguments. I begin with the arguments from diversity, which have
been developed by Schellenberg (2000), Feldman (2007), Christianson (2009), and
others. A recent example is sketched below.
7. The argument from religious diversity
Each of the major
religions can boast good numbers of people who are intelligent, religiously
well-informed, and otherwise competent assessors of evidence, who nevertheless
disagree with each other over which religion is true. This systematic
disagreement reveals that a substantial percentage of those party to the
disagreement must be mistaken. This in turn strongly suggests that there is a
good deal of unreliability in the processes used to arrive at their competing
positions. But then, as Sanford Goldberg, a recent proponent of this argument,
summarizes
…insofar as the parties to the
dispute are otherwise quite competent epistemically, it begins to seem that no
side should be particularly confident that it has gotten things right on the
matter at hand. The facts constituting the systematic disagreement are (second
order) evidence on the basis of which one’s confidence in one’s having attained
truth would be unwarranted. And insofar as no side should be particularly
confident, it seems that no side should believe. (2014, 286)
Goldberg concludes that
such religious disagreement constitutes a defeater for the beliefs concerned.
The X-claim argument and
Goldberg’s version of the argument from religious diversity are clearly
related. Goldberg’s argument takes disagreements between intelligent and well-informed
disputants to generate some sort of defeater for religious belief. The X-claim
argument similarly concludes that (many) religious beliefs at least face a
rationality defeater, and it may draw on the very same disagreements as
evidence. However, note that the X-claim argument appeals not just to disagreement but to a much broader range of evidence
of unreliability.
Considered in isolation,
mere disagreement between intelligent and well-informed disputants, if it
discredits the competing beliefs at all, discredits them all, including, in
this case, non-belief or atheism. The X-claim argument, by contrast, brings
into play a wider range of evidence to support, not the view that every party to the dispute has a pretty good
chance of being mistaken, but that those who believe religious X-claims on the
basis of subjective experience and testimony are far more likely to be mistaken
than are the skeptics.
Exclusivists suppose one
religion has it mostly right and the others go seriously wrong. Exclusivists
typically respond to the argument from religious diversity by raising the
following two objections:
The 'proves too much' objection. If systematic disagreement
between the intelligent and well-informed is sufficient to require that we
withhold from believing, then we will have to withhold in many other spheres
too, such as the political, philosophical and moral spheres. Yet surely I can
continue reasonably to maintain my political, philosophical, or moral position
even whilst acknowledging that there is a good number of intelligent
well-informed people that disagree with me. In short, the principle on which
the argument from disagreement is based, if applied consistently, would require
us to embrace an absurdly wide-ranging political, philosophical, and moral
skepticism.
Alvin Plantinga uses a
hypothetical example to elicit the intuition that we might reasonably continue
to hold a moral belief even after discovering others disagree. Suppose you
think it wrong for a counselor to use his position of trust to seduce a client,
but you discover others disagree: they think it a minor peccadillo, like
running a red light when there’s no traffic. Plantinga suggests that even if
you think the dissenters have the same ‘internal markers’ for their beliefs (it
seems no less obvious to them that they are right, even after careful
reflection, etc.), you can reasonably continue to maintain your belief, and
perhaps become even more committed to it after additional reflection.
You may suppose that those others are in some epistemic way less fortunate or
well-placed than you. (Plantinga (2000),
190). But if
you are entitled to stick to your guns in the political, philosophical and
moral case, then why not in religious case?
The problem of self-defeat. Intelligent, well-informed epistemologists disagree
about whether we should withhold belief on discovering that there are
intelligent and well-informed individuals who disagree. But then consistency
requires proponents of the argument from religious diversity to abandon the
very principle on which their argument is based: that where such disagreement
occurs, belief should be abandoned.
Whether or not the
argument from religious diversity succumbs to the above two objections, the
X-claim argument avoids them.
The X-claim argument
avoids the 'proves too much' objection for it does not require that where there
is disagreement between the intelligent and well-informed, belief should be
withheld. The X-claim argument allows the bar requiring that belief be withheld
to be set much higher than that, as the following analogy makes clear.
Suppose a space probe is
sent to a remote planet on which it is suspected life might exist. The probe
transmits back to Earth data from which scientists subsequently draw very
different conclusions. Some scientists believe the data reveals there are trees
are growing at the landing site. Others believe the data reveals not trees but
flowers. Still others believe the data reveals neither trees nor flowers but
ferns. There are also scientists who are undecided, and scientists who believe,
on the basis of the transmitted data, that no plant life is present at the
landing site.
Clearly, not all these
intelligent, well-informed scientists can be correct. Their disagreement
reveals many must be mistaken. That disagreement, considered in isolation,
casts a shadow of suspicion over all their respective verdicts.
On discovering their
disagreement, should these scientists withhold from believing their respective
verdicts? Perhaps not. Perhaps such skepticism is, at this point, unwarranted.
After all, if they are to abandon a verdict whenever they discover intelligent,
well-informed people disagree, then the fact that there’s disagreement among
the scientists about whether verdicts should be abandoned in such circumstances
should lead them to abandon their verdict that such verdicts should be
abandoned (the problem of self-defeat).
But now suppose further
evidence is discovered indicating that the lab where all these scientists are
working has been infected with some as yet unidentified causal agent that has a
strange psychological effect – it strongly inclines scientists to believe they
have discovered one or another form of plant life whether or not they’ve
actually done so. This agent, whatever it turns out to be, produces a high
proportion of false positive beliefs.
The shadow of suspicion
generated by their mere disagreement fell on all the scientists’ respective
verdicts. This new evidence shifts that shadow away from the verdict of those
scientists who were skeptical about the presence of plant life and deepens it
very considerably over the verdicts of those claiming there is one or other
form of plant life growing at the landing site. Perhaps, prior to this last
discovery, all of the scientists concerned might reasonably have maintained
their respective beliefs about plant life on the planet, notwithstanding their
disagreement. But, given this new evidence, surely those scientists who
previously judged there to be plant life present should now be revising their
verdict.
The X-claim argument
similarly points, not merely to disagreement between intelligent and
well-informed individuals about which of various competing X-claims, if any,
are true, but to evidence of some sort of causal factor or factors (perhaps as
yet unidentified) strongly inclining humans to believe X-claims on the basis of
S&T irrespective of whether those claims are true, with the result that
there’s a high proportion of false positive beliefs. My suggestion is that this
additional evidence should lead X-claim believers to withhold, even if mere
disagreement concerning competing X-claims should not.
The X-claim argument is
also immune to the problem of self-defeat. It is not self-defeating in the way
the argument from religious diversity is supposed to be, for it does not depend
on the thought that where there is disagreement between the intelligent and
well-informed, belief should be withheld.
8. Naturalistic debunking arguments
A number of arguments
against religious belief have been offered grounded in the thought that
religious belief can, in one way or another, be explained naturalistically.
Marx and Freud offer such
naturalistic explanations. According to Marx, religious belief is a product of
social dysfunction and dislocation. According to Freud, religious belief is a
result of wish fulfilment. More recently, evolutionary psychology has offered
naturalistic explanations of religious beliefs in terms of, for example, the
HADD (mentioned above) and minimally counterintuitive concepts[9].
Such naturalistic explanations may be supposed not just to explain religious
belief, but to explain it away. For example, in Breaking the Spell (2010) Daniel Dennett argues that findings in
the cognitive science of religion support atheism.
Why suppose such
explanations don’t just explain religious belief but explain it away? As
characterized by Guy Kahane, debunking arguments are ‘arguments that show the
causal origins of a belief to be an undermining defeater.’ (2010, 106) While
all beliefs have explanations, not all have explanations in terms of processes
that, as Kahane puts it, ‘track the truth’. If someone decides on whether or
not to believe that p by flipping a
coin, there would be no connection between their means of forming belief and
the truth. Kahane calls processes that are not truth-tracking ‘off track’.
According to Kahane, the second-order belief that a certain belief was formed
by an off-track process can constitute an undermining defeater for that belief
if the off track process ‘leaves no space for the contribution of processes
that would, in this context, track the truth’.
To illustrate, in the
coin-flipping example, the process generating the belief is not just off-track,
but such that it squeezes out contributions from processes that are, as it
were, on-track. That's not always the case. You might explain my belief that
there are fish in the local river by pointing to my strong desire to believe
there are fish there. Now it may be true that my strong desire to believe did
indeed play an important causal role in producing my belief: without it, I
would not have investigated the river. But while that strong desire is an
off-track mechanism playing some significant role in the production of my
belief, it doesn't preclude an on-track process playing a role, and so it
doesn't preclude my knowing there are fish in the river because, say, after
investigating as a result of my strong desire I actually caught one.
If Kahane is correct,
Marxist, Freudian, or evolutionary explanations of religious belief will
succeed in debunking religious belief only if they invoke off-track processes leaving no room for processes that are
on-track.
How might religious
belief be defended against such naturalistic debunking arguments? Such argument
are often criticized on the grounds that, while the explanations offered might
account for religious belief, little reason is supplied for supposing the
explanations are actually correct.
Plantinga raises this objection with respect to Freud who, Plantinga notes,
offers ‘no more than the most perfunctory argument’ that religious belief
actually is a product of wish fulfilment (Plantinga (2000b), 195-6).
Evolutionary explanations of religious belief have similarly been criticized
for offering little more than ‘just so’ stories lacking evidential support.
(see e.g. Ratcliffe (2006), 94).
A second standard line
of defence against naturalistic debunking arguments is to suggest that, even if
the explanation offered is correct, that’s not yet to say religious belief is
debunked. There may be reason to distrust religious beliefs that are purely a product of social dysfunction,
or wish fulfilment, or an HADD, as these are mechanisms we can have little
confidence will produce true beliefs. But why should the involvement of these
off-track processes preclude the involvement of processes that are on-track?
So, for example,
Plantinga says about Freud’s explanation of religious belief that while wish
fulfilment might not generally be aimed at truth, in the case of theistic
belief it could be. Plantinga suggests God may have designed us with a deep
need to believe in him and be aware of his presence – that's how God has
arranged for us to come to know him. If so, then the mechanism governing the
formation of theistic belief is aimed at true belief even if that belief arises
from wish fulfilment. And so it can still deliver knowledge. (Plantinga (2000b),
197) Psychologist Justin Barrett similarly insists that finding
natural mechanisms that account for religious beliefs fails to debunk them:
‘Christian theology teaches that people were crafted by God to be in a loving
relationship with him and other people… Why wouldn’t God, then, design us in
such a way as to find belief in divinity quite natural?’[10] Philosopher
Michael
Murray concurs: ‘God set up the natural conditions so that, pace the objection, natural selection
does select for reliable religious belief forming mechanisms’ (Murray (2007),
398). In short: the correctness of an explanation of religious belief in terms some
natural process that is usually off-track does not preclude that process forming
part of some larger, divinely-engineered process that is on-track.
Whether
or not the above two objections to naturalistic debunking arguments against
religious belief succeed, the X-claim argument, while closely related to such debunking
arguments, is immune to them. Of course the X-claim argument has something in common with naturalistic
debunking arguments. Both aim to provide a kind of defeater for religious
belief, and both aim to do this by providing evidence of there being something
unreliable or untrustworthy about the way religious beliefs are formed.
However, unlike
Freudian, Marxist, and evolutionary debunking arguments targeting some specific
religious belief, the X-claim argument does not require some particular naturalistic
explanation of the target belief be correct. The X-claim argument merely points
to our systematic unreliability with respect to religious and other X-claim
beliefs (when grounded in S&T) and concludes that this supplies a rationality
defeater for anyone who believes an X-claim on the basis of S&T. It’s evidence
of our general human proneness to false belief in X-claims when grounded in S&T,
rather than evidence of the correctness of any particular explanation for the
target X-claim religious belief, that is supposed to generate the defeater. It
matters not what the correct explanation for the target belief is. Indeed, it might
actually be a product of some divinely-engineered, wholly supernatural, on-track
process (the operation of a sensus divinitatis,
say). My suggestion is: given the range of evidence we have regarding belief in
X-claims, an X-claim belief grounded in S&T - even if it is as a matter of
fact a product of such a divinely-engineered, on-track process - still faces a rationality defeater.
So it appears the
X-claim argument is invulnerable to both the above objections to naturalistic
debunking arguments.
9. A novel argument?
I'll address one final objection: that the X-claim argument rests on the
argument from diversity and naturalistic debunking arguments. Why do I suppose
we are systematically unreliable judges regarding X-claims? Isn't part
of my case for supposing we're unreliable judges of the truth regarding
X-claims provided by X-claim diversity? Further, doesn't my case for that
unreliability depend on my supposing some sort of non-truth-tracking natural
mechanism is responsible for producing many positive X-claim beliefs? But then don't
my reasons for believing we are unreliable judges of X-claims boil down to just
(i) that there substantial disagreement about X-claims, and (ii) that X-claims
have been naturalistically debunked? In which case, my argument for religious
skepticism isn't novel: it rests on the argument from diversity and naturalistic
debunking arguments
This objection is based on
misunderstanding. My claim is that we are highly prone to false positive
X-claim beliefs when they are grounded in just S&T, and this provides us
with a rationality defeater for such beliefs. Note, first, that the claim that
such beliefs can be explained naturalistically plays no role in my argument. It's
not the likely correctness of some naturalistic explanation for our proneness to
false positive X-claim beliefs that provides the rationality defeater, but that
proneness itself, which various naturalistic mechanisms have been invoked to
explain. Indeed, even if it turned out our proneness to false positive X-claim beliefs
had some non-natural cause (it turned out, say, that some mischievous demon is
causing us mistakenly to suppose our dead ancestors, gods, etc. are revealing
themselves), that wouldn't undermine the X-claim argument. Secondly, while
diversity of X-claim belief plays some role in supporting the claim that we're
systematically prone to error when it comes to X-claim beliefs, it is not - as
it is in the argument from religious diversity - diversity alone that is supposed to generate a defeater, but that diversity
in combination with considerable evidence for a proneness to false positive beliefs. It's that further evidence that gives the X-claim argument two
significant advantages over arguments from diversity: it avoids both the
'proves too much' objection and the problem of self-defeat.
Conclusion
I hope this paper will give pause for
thought to those who believe that standard objections to the argument from
religious diversity and naturalistic debunking arguments have effectively
neutralised those arguments against religious belief. Perhaps they have. However,
there appears to be another argument in the vicinity that is rather more
formidable: an argument that has, until now, been overlooked.[11]
References
BARRETT,
JUSTIN L. (2004) Why Would Anyone Believe in God? (Lanham Sylvialand: AltaMira
Press)
BOYER,
PASCAL (2002) Religion Explained, The Evolutionary Origins of Religious Thought.
New edition. (London: Vintage).
CHRISTIANSON,
DAVID (2009) 'Disagreement as Evidence: The Epistemology of Controversy', Philosophy
Compass, 5, 756 –756.
CLARK,
KELLY JAMES AND BARRETT, JUSTIN. L. (2010) 'Reformed Epistemology and The
Cognitive Science of Religion', Faith and
Philosophy, 27, 174-189.
CONAN
DOYLE, ARTHUR (2001) The Coming of The
Fairies (Calgary, Alberta: Theophania Publishing).
DENNETT,
DANIEL (2010) Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural
Phenomenon (London:
Penguin).
FELDMAN,
RICHARD (2006) Epistemological Puzzles About Disagreement. In Epistemology
Futures, HETHERINGTON, STEPHEN (ed.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
FRENCH,
CHRISTOPHER C. and STONE, ANNA (2013) Anomalistic
Psychology (Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan).
GOLDBERG, SANFORD C. (2014)
'Does Externalist Epistemology Rationalize Religious Commitment?', in Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue,
CALLAHAN, LAURA FRANCES and O'CONNER, TIMOTHY (eds.) (Oxford: Oxford University
Press) 279-298.
KAHANE, GUY (2010) 'Evolutionary
debunking Arguments', Nous, 45,
103-125.
LACKEY,
JENNIFER (2003) 'A Minimal Expression of Non-Reductionism in the Epistemology of
Testimony', Nous, 37, 706-723.
LASONEN AARNIO, M. (2010) 'Unreasonable Knowledge', Philosophical Perspectives, 24. 1-21.
MURRAY,
M. J. (2007) 'Four Arguments That the Cognitive Psychology of Religion
Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief', in BULBULIA. J. et al.,
(eds). Evolution of Religion: Studies, Theories, and Critiques
(Santa Margarita, CA: The Collins Foundation
Press), 394-398.
NICKELL,
JOE. (2001) Real-Life X-Files: Investigating the
Paranormal (Lexington
KY: University
Press of Kentucky).
PINKER,
STEVEN. (2004) 'The Evolutionary Psychology of Religion', speech
given at the annual meeting of the Freedom from Religion Foundation, Madison,
Wisconsin, October 29, 2004, on Pinker’s receipt of ‘The Emperor’s New Clothes
Award’. Available online at:
http://pinker.wjh.harvard.edu/articles/media/2004_10_29_religion.htm
PLANTINGA,
ALVIN. (2000a) 'Pluralism', In The
Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity, QUINN, PHILIP L. AND
MEEKER, KEVIN (eds.) (New York: Oxford University Press), 172-192.
(2000b) Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
RATCLIFFE, MATTHEW (2006)
'Neurotheology', In MCNAMARA PATRICK (ed.) Where
God And Science Meet: The Neurology Of Religious Experience (Westport:
Praeger), 81-104.
SCHELLENBERG,
J. L. (2000) 'Religious Experience and Religious Diversity: A Reply to Alston',
in The Philosophical Challenge of
Religious Diversity, QUINN, PHILIP L. and MEEKER, KEVIN. (eds.) (New York:
Oxford University Press), 208–217.
WILLIAMSON, TIMOTHY
(2000)
Knowledge and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
[1] Source: Jan-Feb issue of The Skeptical Inquirer 2006.
[2] I choose this title partly because such beings
were a focus of The X-Files TV
programme.
[3] Robert Carroll, 'Pranks, Frauds, and Hoaxes
from Around the World', Skeptical
Inquirer vol 28.4 July/Aug 2004.
[4] Related to me by Professor Chris French who was
involved in the programme.
[5] See Joe Nickell, 'The
Flatwoods UFO Monster', Skeptical
Inquirer vol 24.6, Nov/Dec 2000.
[6]
Of course, if a certain deity
exists, then everyone who disbelieves in that deity holds a false negative
belief. Still, the track record of disbelieving in deities remains strong given
the vast majority of deities in which people disbelieve don't exist.
[7]
Safety conditions on knowledge are
associated particularly with Williamson, Sosa, and Pritchard. A simple example
of a safety condition says S knows P only if S
is safe from error; that is, there
must be no risk that S believes falsely in a similar case. For an
example of the safety view see Williamson (2000),
[8] I am grateful to an anonymous referee for
raising this objection.
[9] Minimally
counter-intuitive concepts are concepts that mostly fit with our usual
preconceptions about objects but break with them in one or two ways. This makes
them attention grabbing and easy to remember. Talking animals and non-corporeal
agents are examples. See Boyer
(2002)
[10] Quoted by Robin Marantz Henig ‘Darwin’s God’ in The Guardian, 4 March 2007.
[11] My thanks to John Hawthorne and an Oxford University
New Insights and Directions for Religious Epistemology seminar for comments an
earlier draft of this paper, and also for helpful and detailed feedback from
Max Baker-Hytch.
Comments
If I am right, then the Christian cannot be said to know that his religion is true, even if in fact it is. But he will no doubt reject my argument, on the grounds that it is his experience, that he finds it incredible that any conflicting experience could have the same quality, and that he simply infers that other purported experiences incompatible with Christianity were inferior.
I do not think that you can prove him unreasonable. He has evidence that you (in the nature of things) don't, and plausibly considers himself better placed than you to evaluate it.
The only defeater that I find convincing for such belief is the demonstration that it has implications known to be false. One such is the belief that there is such a place as heaven, into which the disciples saw Jesus ascending. But I use this argument with caution - I have discovered that it strains such friendships as I have with Christians.
Could I add further to your first comment on the sixth objection that, not only do people report agencies differently, they also report what the agencies intend very differently, often contradicting each other.
Could not someone mirror this argument against well-established and accepted scientific knowledge too, by focusing on a particular cognitive function? Plantinga offers a general argument against the rationality of beliefs generally, if evolution and naturalism are true, but perhaps a Y-claim could be that we have a history of false-positive beliefs in empirical matters, given the overwhelming number of (it turns out) incorrect scientific theories about the world? So it would be unreasonable to believe the earth is round.
Perhaps this Y-claim suffers from being too vague, while the X-claim is handily specific and well-tested.
You treat religious beliefs as though they are scientific hypotheses and thus you judge religion by the standards of science with regard to with no regard to magisteria, purpose or function,I have the empirical evidence to warrant belief in God as sound and valid, 200 studies peer reviewed journals. See The Trace of God, by Joseph Hinman, on amazon
I have written a response to your argument mostly dealing with what I believe is an inadequate reply to the 5th objection you predict. I would be honored to hear your thoughts on it.
In Christ,
Niko
http://etinmorteego.tumblr.com/post/150203244177/response-to-stephen-laws-x-claim-argument-against
I'd like to make some more specific comments.
1. You ask about what the defeater-defeater may be. I'd like to suggest that one defeater-defeater is that the alternative of a non-religious reality appears to be much more unreasonable and based on much more shaky truth-tracking processes. Metaphysics is too difficult for us to be able to judge the reasonableness of a particular belief in isolation. It is in practice much more effective to *compare* the reasonableness of mutually exclusive beliefs. Currently the strongest religious belief in metaphysics is philosophical theism (not “biblical Christianity”) and the strongest non-religious belief in metaphysics is scientific naturalism (the view that reality is exhausted by the objects the physical sciences study). In my judgment the conceptual problems that plague the latter belief are far more serious than the former, and this realization defeats any defeaters I may have for theism.
2. The diversity of claims in some field should not worry us too much since they may well not contradict each other. For example, one person may describe the peak of a mountain as rounded and another person may describe it as pointy, and they may both be right - since the first may be observing the mountain from the south and the other from the east. The same thing can be experienced differently be different people, and thus may be described differently. Religious language concerns the metaphysically ultimate nature of reality, and it is only to be expected that such language may not only poetic but also superficially diverse. For example the metaphysically ultimate nature of a religious reality may have both personal and non-personal aspects, and different religious discourses may concentrate on the one or the other dimension. Or consider a much easier field which is the nature of the physical world, and observe that here scientists increasingly disagree about its most basic characteristics (which moreover clearly do contradict each other). So, for example, they disagree about whether there is one universe (the one we see around us) or many parallel ones, about whether our own universe stays put or perhaps in every instant multiplies itself into a humongously large number of almost identical copies (see the so-called “many worlds” interpretation of quantum mechanics), about the fundamental question of whether physical reality itself (not the equations) is deterministic or not, whether time has a beginning or not (time in our universe probably has a beginning, but if physical reality consists of many parallel universes then the question is still open), about whether space is finite or not, about how many physical dimensions there are (there is even a suggestion that we live in a two-dimensional hologram), and even whether the universe is real or perhaps a computer simulation (see “computer simulation argument”). But from this confusing and self-contradictory diversity of scientific opinion it certainly does not follow that scientists must be imagining things.
Given Plato's cave I think it is clear that many alternative realities are consistent with the whole of our current experience of life, and thus that many different descriptions of reality may be true. The best we can do is discuss which of them is more reasonable, and have faith that what is more reasonable is also more probably true. A matter of faith which, incidentally, fits naturally to theism but not to atheism.