13. The Consciousness Conundrum
Philosophy Gym category:
Warm up
Moderate
More challenging
Scientists are grappling with “the
problem of consciousness”: the problem of explaining how that walnut-shaped
lump of grey matter between your ears is capable of producing a rich inner
world of conscious experiences. Will they ever solve this mystery? Some think
it’s only a matter of time. Yet there are arguments that appear to show that
consciousness is something that it is in principle impossible for science to explain.
The private realm of consciousness
Take a look at something red: a ripe tomato, for example. As you look at
this object, you are conscious of having a certain experience – a colour
experience. As the philosopher Thomas Nagel[i]
(xx) explains, there’s something it is
like to have this experience, something for
you, the subject.
We spend our lives immersed in a
vibrant flow of such experiences: the smell of a flower, the taste of an
orange, the rough sensation of wood under ones fingertips, a zinging pain, a
melancholic moment. An interesting feature of this rich inner life we lead is
that it seems peculiarly hidden from others. Others can observe my body and
outward behaviour. But my experiences are hidden inside. Indeed, they would
appear to be “hidden inside” in very strong sense. For they are not physically hidden, as, say, my brain is
physically hidden inside my skull. Things that are physically hidden can in
principle be revealed. Surgeons might one day be able to open up my skull and
observe what physically goes on inside me when I have a colour experience. But
they can never enter my mind and observe what the experience is like for me, from my point of view.
What is it like to be a bat?
There
are also conscious experiences no human being has ever enjoyed. Take bats for
example. Bats manage to find their way around in the dark by using
echo-location. The bat emits a sound (inaudible to humans), and the loudness of
the echoes and the direction from which they come allow the bat to build up a
picture of its environment.
[SUGGESTED
ILLUSTRATION: BAT EMITTING SOUND (SEMI-CIRCLES) AND THEN HEARING THE ECHO
BOUNCING BACK (MORE SEMI-CIRCLES)]
Echo-location allows bats to
“see” using sound. Now ask yourself: What must it be like to be a bat, to
experience the world as the bat does? No doubt there is something it’s like for
the bat when it “sees” using echo-location, but, as Nagel points out, we can’t
know what it’s like. We could discover everything there is to know about what
happens in a bat’s nervous system when it “sees” using sound. But that still
wouldn’t allow us to know what the experience is like for the bat. It seems the
bat’s experience, like yours and mine, is essentially private.
The
realm of conscious experience is responsible for what continues to be one of
the most profound and intractable of mysteries, a mystery with which both
philosophers and scientists are currently very much engaged. The mystery
concerns how our physical bodies and our conscious minds are related. The problem,
as we shall see, is that, on the one hand, it seems your conscious mind must be
physical, yet, on the other hand, it seems it cannot be.
Two competing theories of consciousness
Scientists tell us that when you looked at that red
object a minute or so ago, the following happened. Light of certain wavelengths
was reflected off the object into your eye where it was focused onto your
retina to produce an image. Your retina is covered with millions of light
sensitive cells, some of which are sensitive to differences in wavelength. The
light falling on to these cells caused them to emit electrical impulses which
then flowed down the nerves linking your eye to the back of your brain. That
caused something to happen in your brain.
But what about your experience? According
to the philosopher René Descartes (1596-1650) your conscious mind is a distinct
entity capable of existing on its own, independently of anything physical. So,
on Descartes’ view, after something happened in your brain, something else had
to happen: your brain caused something to happen in your mind. Your mind and
brain may interact. But they are not identical.
[ILLUSTRATE]
According to many contemporary scientists and philosophers, however,
it’s a mistake to think of conscious experience in this way. Professor Susan
Greenfield, for example, insists that “you are your brain”. Your experience
isn’t something extra – something on top of what happens physically. Rather,
the mental just is part of what’s
going on physically.
[ILLUSTRATE]
Certainly, scientists sometimes
reveal that what might seem like two distinct things are actually one and the
same thing. Take the morning star and the evening star, for example. For a long
time, we thought these heavenly bodies were distinct. Then astronomers
discovered that they are one and the same object seen twice over (the planet
Venus).
Scientists have also established that certain properties are identical.
For example, they have discovered that heat is a molecular motion, electricity
is a flow of electrons and water is H2O.
So why shouldn’t it also turn out that pain just is a certain state of
the brain? Admittedly, pain doesn’t seem like a brain state. But so what? After
all, heat doesn’t seem like molecular motion – yet that’s just what it is.
Substances and properties
We have been looking at two competing theories about consciousness. First, there are those who believe that your conscious experiences are nothing over and above what goes on in your brain. Second, there are those who, like Descartes, deny this. But before we get to the arguments for and against these two positions, it will be useful if we distinguish two rather different versions of the second position.
On Descartes’s view, your mind and body are distinct substances: each is capable of existing
independently of the other. Your conscious mind could, in principle, be
detached from everything physical and exist on its own. This position is called
substance dualism.
Hardly any scientists or philosophers are now prepared to accept
substance dualism. But there are still plenty of philosophers (and at least
some scientists) around who believe that there are two distinct and irreducible
kinds of property: physical
properties and mental properties. This position is called property dualism.
According to property dualism, there’s only one kind
of stuff – physical stuff. But objects made out of this physical stuff can have
two quite different sorts of property. On the view of the property dualist,
there are both mental properties and physical properties: the mental properties
of a human being are extra properties that exist in addition to all of his or
her physical properties.
An argument against dualism
Let’s
now turn to one of the most popular arguments against all forms of dualism.
In
effect, dualists want to introduce an extra layer of facts in addition to the
physical facts. There are physical facts: the facts about physical substances
and properties. But according to dualists, there are also non-physical substances
and/or properties. The facts about these non-physical substances/properties are
facts in addition to the physical
facts.
Many scientists and philosophers consider the
suggestion that there are such “additional” facts thoroughly unscientific. Why is this?
Suppose that at a dinner party I am given the choice
between a glass of wine and a glass of beer.
[ILLUSTRATE: “WINE OR BEER?”]
I like both, but decide on
this occasion to have wine. I reach out and select a glass of white.
Scientists tell us that such physical movements have
physical causes. The movement of my arm was caused by the action of muscles in
my arm, which was itself brought about by electrical activity in the efferent
nerves running from my brain.
[ILLUSTRATE]
This electrical activity was in
turn caused by physical activity in my brain, which was caused brought about by
further preceding physical causes, including the stimulation of my nervous
system by light reflected off the glasses on the tray in front of me and the
sound of someone speaking to me. These physical causes in turn had physical
causes, which in turn had physical causes, and so on.
Indeed, it seems that if scientists were furnished with knowledge of the
laws of nature plus all the physical facts about my body and my environment as
they were, say, one minute prior to my deciding to reach out and grasp that
glass of wine, it would be possible in
principle for them to figure out that my arm would do what it did. That
movement of my arm was fixed in advance by how things stood physically.
But if this is correct – if what happens physically is fixed in advance by
the preceding physical facts – then there is no possibility of any non-physical
fact affecting how things turn out. The non-physical must be causally
irrelevant to what goes on physically.
But if dualism is true, then my conscious mind is
non-physical. But then it follows that my mind
can make no difference to what goes on physically. Suppose, for example,
that I had decided to pick up a glass of beer instead. Because of the physical
facts, my arm would have been compelled to reach out and grasped that glass of
wine anyway.
ILLUSTRATE: THINK BUBBLE “BUT I WANTED A GLASS OF
BEER”]
Indeed, if dualism is true,
you could take my mind away altogether and my body would still carry on in exactly the same way.
But
this is absurd, surely? My mind can and does affect how
my body behaves. But as it is only the physical facts that affect how things
turn out physically, the only way in which the facts about what happens in my
mind can have a physical effect is if
they are themselves physical facts. But then it follows that dualism (both
substance and property) is false.
Many scientists and philosophers are convinced by
this and other arguments that the facts about what goes on in the conscious
mind must ultimately be physical facts. However, the issue is far from settled.
There are also powerful arguments that appear to show that these scientists and
philosophers are mistaken. One of the best known arguments is presented by the
philosopher Frank Jackson. Jackson’s argument runs as follows.
Mary and the black and white room
A girl called “Mary” is born. Before she has any visual experiences,
Mary is placed in a black and white room by scientists who wish to study her.
The scientists arrange that Mary never has a colour experience (they hide
Mary’s pink hands from her by using white gloves, and so on). Mary experiences
only black, white and shades of grey.
[ILLUSTRATION: MARY IN HER ROOM.]
Mary grows up in her black and
white environment. She develops a fascination with science. Indeed Mary
eventually becomes the world’s greatest brain expert. She finds out everything
there is to know about what goes on inside a human brain when the human
experiences the colour red. She discovers all the physical facts about the
brains of colour perceivers: how their neurones are firing, how the brain
chemistry is balanced, and so on.
Then, one day, one of the scientists
studying her brings a ripe tomato into her black and white world.
Mary
is stunned. She now has an experience that she’s
never had before. She finds out what it is like to have a colour experience.
Mary discovers a new fact: the fact that the experience of red is like this (I’m looking at that red
object again). But Mary previously knew all the physical facts. So the fact
that the experience is like this is
not a physical fact. Facts about the qualitative character of our conscious
experiences – about what it is like to have them – are not physical facts.
The explanatory gap
Jackson seems to have shown that there are more facts than just the
physical facts. But there’s a further conclusion you might wish to draw.
Jackson’s story also appears to show that not
everything can be explained or understood by science. We can’t explain or
understand why red things look like this
by appealing only to the physical facts about us. We come up against what
contemporary philosophers call an explanatory
gap at this point.
Contrast the case of heat. Identifying heat with
vigorous molecular motion allows us to deduce the various properties of heat.
Discovering what’s going on at the molecular level allows us to understand why
objects that are heated char and blacken, why they tend to make nearby objects
hot, and so on.
But a full understanding of the goings-on in the human brain will not
allow one to understand why pain feels the way it does or explain why ripe
tomatoes produce this sort of visual
experience. Mary knows everything there is to know about what goes on in the
brains of colour perceivers, but this knowledge does not allow her to
understand what an experience of red is actually like. Indeed, none of the
physical facts she discovers go any way towards explaining why such
physiological states should be accompanied by conscious states at all.
The analogy with life
Jackson’s argument appears to show both that
(1) There are more facts than
the physical facts,
and
(2) It is in
principle impossible for the physical sciences to account for
consciousness.
But many scientists are
dismissive of such conclusions. They often suggest the current situation with
respect to consciousness is similar to the situation 200 years ago with respect
to life. Life at that time constituted a
great mystery. We simply had no idea how mere physical matter could be
organized in such a way as to produce an animate, living thing. Many thought
that something extra – a mysterious and supernatural “life force” –had to be
added to a physical object in order to imbue it with life.
Today, of course, the explanation of life is mostly
within our grasp. Darwin’s theory of natural selection, advances in genetics,
and so on have allowed us to explain many of the properties of life. Even where
a scientific explanation of some particular feature of life currently eludes
us, we can at least now see how such an explanation might in principle be
constructed just by appealing to physical facts.
Many scientists argue that, similarly, just because a scientific
explanation of consciousness now
eludes us doesn’t mean that no such explanation is possible. There’s no need to
suppose that consciousness must be something mysterious and supernatural that
exists in addition to what we find
within the natural, physical world. These are early days in the scientific
investigation of consciousness. Our current inability to imagine how
consciousness might be explained by appealing only to physical facts may simply
be due to our lack of an adequate theory, just as in the case of life.
Conclusion: a mystery
We have been grappling with mystery of how to
accommodate consciousness within the physical universe. Many scientists believe
that consciousness must ultimately be reducible to and explicable in terms of
the physical. Indeed, given that the conscious mind is able causally to affect
what goes on physically, it seems it must itself be physical.
But
there are powerful objections to this belief. Jackson’s story about Mary and
the black and white room seems to show that it is in principle impossible for
the facts about the character of our conscious experience to be reduced to and
explained in terms of physical facts. It seems there must be more facts than
just the physical.
Many
scientists reject all forms of dualism out of hand. But unless they can show
what is wrong with Jackson’s argument (and, indeed, the other very convincing
looking-arguments that are around), their dismissive attitude towards dualism
looks hasty. Blindly to reject such arguments looks more like prejudice than a
rationally held position.
Of
course, it may be that there’s something wrong with Jackson’s argument (see the
text box below). But the onus is on those who reject all forms of dualism to
show precisely what is wrong with it.
And of course, showing what’s wrong with such arguments is the job not of
empirical science, but of logic and the philosophy.
So
can science ever solve the mystery of consciousness? The answer is, perhaps.
But not by itself. Science will need the help of philosophy.
[[START OF BIG TEXT BOX
(DOUBLE PAGE SPREAD?)
THINKING TOOLS: The masked man fallacy
This section explains what
may be wrong with Jackson’s argument. There is a popular form of argument often
used to establish that two things are not identical. You search for a property
that one of the two things has that the other lacks. If you can find such a
property, it follows that the items in question are non-identical.
For
example, if you want to establish that K2 and Everest are distinct mountains, all
you need to do is find a property one mountain possesses that the other lacks.
For example, you might argue like this:
Everest
has the property of being over 29,000ft
high
K2
doesn’t have the property of being over
29,000ft high
Therefore:
Everest is not identical with K2
This is a sound argument:
each of the two premises is true and the logic is impeccable. The argument
really does establish that Everest and K2 are distinct.
Those
who argue that mind and body are non-identical often appeal to the same form of
argument. Here, for example, is an argument (often attributed to Descartes)
called the argument from doubt.
I don’t doubt that I exist. After all, by trying to doubt
that I exist, I demonstrate that I do exist, so my attempt at doubting that I
exist must inevitably be self-defeating.
I do doubt that my body exists. It seems to me that I
might be a disembodied mind, with all my experiences being generated by some
sort of malevolent demon (for more on this sort of doubt, see chapter XX
“Brainsnatched”).
But
then it seems that my body has a property that I lack: my body has the property
of being something the existence of which
I doubt. I lack this property. So it surely follows – by an argument
analogous to that about Everest and K2 – that I’m not identical with my body.
Here’s the argument laid out more formally:
My
body possesses the property of being
something the existence of which I doubt
I
don’t possess the property of being
something the existence of which I doubt
Therefore:
I am not identical with my body.
This sort of argument has
convinced many that mind and body are non-identical. But, despite the
similarity to the Everest/K2 argument, this is a bad argument. What we have
here is an example of the masked man
fallacy. Here’s another example of the fallacy. Suppose I witness a bank
being robbed. This leads me to believe that the masked man robbed the bank.
Later, detectives inform me that their lead suspect is my father. Horrified, I
try to prove that my father cannot be the masked man. I point out that the
masked man has a property my father lacks: he’s someone I believe to have
robbed the bank. I argue like this:
The
masked man has the property of being
someone I believe robbed the bank
My
father lacks the property of being
someone I believe robbed the bank
Therefore:
my father is not identical with the masked man.
This is obviously a bad
argument, despite sharing the same form as the sound Everest/K2 argument. It
could yet turn out that my father is
the masked man, despite the fact that both premises are true. Why is this?
The
problem is that this form of argument does not work for all kinds of property. It works for properties such as being more than 29,000ft high. It does
not work with properties such as being
someone I believe to have robbed the bank. More generally, this form of
argument is invalid whenever the property in question involves someone’s psychological attitude towards a
thing.
For
example, in the masked man case, I try to show that my father and the masked
man are distinct by pointing out that I have an attitude towards one that I
don’t have towards the other: I believe one robbed the bank but not the other.
But such attitudes are incapable of revealing whether or not the items in
question really are distinct. Here are a couple of other examples:
John
Wayne is someone John knows appeared in “True Grit”
Marion
Morrison is not someone John knows appeared in “True Grit”
Therefore:
John Wayne isn’t Marion Morrison
Heat
is widely recognised to cook food
Molecular
motion is not widely recognised to cook food
Therefore:
heat isn’t molecular motion
Both these arguments have
true premises but false conclusions (“John Wayne” is the stage name of Marion
Morrison). The problem, again, is that what someone may know or believe or
recognise about one thing but not another is not the sort of property one can
use to establish the non-identity of those things. The argument from doubt
involves the same fallacy.
What
of Jackson’s argument about Mary? Does it also involve the masked man fallacy?
I think that, as it stands, it does. But you should check for yourself. Of
course, none of this is to say that I believe dualism is now defeated. There
may be better arguments for dualism than Jackson’s, arguments that don’t
involve the masked man fallacy. [END OF TEXT BOX (FULL PAGE?)]
What to read next?
This chapter might usefully be
read in conjunction with chapter XX “Could a Machine Think?” Look for where
some of the arguments overlap.
In chapter XX
“Do We Ever Deserve to be Punished?” I briefly discuss the discovery that the
universe is not after all governed by strict and exceptionless laws, but merely
by probabilistic laws. So it turns out that the most that someone furnished
with full information about my physical body and environment could ever predict
about my future behaviour is what I will probably
do. After reading chapter XX, you might wish to return to this chapter to
consider the question: Does this discovery undermine the argument against
dualism presented above? Even if it does, might some version of that argument
still be salvaged?
Further Reading
Jackson’s
story about Mary and the black and white room appears in:
·
“Epiphenomenal Qualia”, in W.
Lycan (ed.), Mind and Cognition
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1990).
For a breezy
and yet quite thorough introduction to the problem of consciousness, see:
·
David Papineau and Howard
Selina, Introducing Consciousness
(Cambridge: Icon, 2000).
An
interesting collection of pieces on the mind can be found in the now quite old
but nevertheless still excellent:
·
Douglas R. Hofstadter and
Daniel Dennett (eds.), The Mind’s I
(London: Penguin, 1981).
The Mind’s I includes Thomas Nagel’s
famous paper, “What is it Like to be a Bat?” [also included as chpt 38 of Nigel
Warburton (ed.), Philosophy: Basic
Readings (London: Routledge, 1999)].
[i] See Tomas Nagel, “What is it Like to be a Bat?”, in Douglas R. Hofstadter and Daniel Dennett
(eds.), The Mind’s I (London:
Penguin, 1981)
Comments
i had a conversation with an "presupptionalist" apologist Jason Lisle a little while and do you think this is stright up question begging
Jason Lisle:“No. Again, we can know that the revelation is from God because any alternative would make knowledge impossible. And we do have knowledge. Thus, the revelation is from God.”
Me:you are begging the question,
Dr. Lisle: No, it is a valid modus tollens.
This guy is in outright denial right?
Thanks
Article of Stephen Law: I certainly agree with this basic thought and believe it is very well illustrated by the argument of Thomas Nagel about the feelings of a bat.
https://lotharlorraine.wordpress.com/?s=bat
Aojamaru: presupositionalists have never, never been able to show that "Biblical Christianity" is the only coherent worldview making sense of knowledge.
Actually, since the Bible is demonstrably full of contradictions, their own worldview is incoherent and self-contradictory.
And I say that as a Christian myself.
Cheers.
What is so interesting about it...is that when goes through the myriad of definitions of what constitutes reality...one invariably comes back to the problem of consciousness...
Strange really, when on realises one uses only 0.045% of ones brain for cognition...
What is interesting...is that even if one is purely materialist (classical) on this issue one is still faced with perplexing results, i.e. if one assumes the existence of "particles"...one finds that "particles" are not strictly inside ones body.
Say, someone wants to measure a particle's position in ones brain, there is a non-zero probability of detecting it in the remotest places of the universe.
Nagel's bat is interesting...but, I would say that if a bat can laugh (most mammals laugh)...then this would perhaps give me an insight as to what is going on in the bat's mind....
I had a read of your article you posted...I found it interesting...
But, I would say that underneath the "mental" and the "material" they are the same.
The former is a qualitative question about the world...and the latter is a quantitative question about the world...
Both concepts are "information" in nature, i.e. knowledge.
You are correct though...one has to jettison the materialist model of the world the approach this issue...
The fact that the materialist model is not working here...is a sign that it is not a good model.
The examples in you piece, I think reflect philosophical confusions concerning "consciousness".
I can liken all your examples with this model.
1/ Pi is a number
2/ Pi is used in trigonometry calculations.
3/ Pi does not correspond to a "point" on a number line.
So, you end up with a philosophical confusion, i.e. Pi is both a number and not a number...
But, if you look at Pi as a relation and not an object then you get somewhere.
If I generalise and assume the diameter of a circle is a dimension and the circumference is an acceleration (circumference is after all a tangent...and a tangent is an acceleration)...then something most interesting happens...
I won't go into the mathematical rigour here...but what you end up is a point on a number line, i.e. Pi=4
This I do think points to the fact that "consciousness" cannot be dealt with as a material thing...in is instead a "relation".
As I have suggested to you previously...reification suffers BIG problems...namely particles don't exist!
Nagel in his latest book comes to the same result...he however does not have the mathematical and physics tools to make his ideas rigorous (and they can be).
"But they can never enter my mind and observe what the experience is like for me, from my point of view. "
This is the truth...because your environmental reality is unique...it is unique for all humans because (using a materialist model) the number of "particles" in your local environment is observer dependent (you wrote this in the quote)...so no wonder one cannot know of another's conscious experience exactly.
This is not to say that such an inkling of another's conscious experience is not open to you...because it is...through the mirror neuron portion of the brain...it is just that you are not cognitively aware of this action, i.e. it is hidden from you.
What is interesting are the recent "Rubber hand experiments"...the results I think are quite important philosophically...
For instance, I think they show that Wittgenstein's idea of "knowledge" is correct...
Here, I am thinking of Moore raising his hand and saying "I know this is my hand."
Wittgenstein would say "No, you do not know it is your hand, you are CERTAIN it is your hand."
And that this certainty is not based on cognition...
But, that this certainty may give you wrong knowledge (here we start getting into Private Language issues)...
In many ways, this links directly to your comments concerning Plantenga's take on evolution...because in many ways the results from the Rubber Hand Experiment undermine the idea that True Belief has any role in evolution...sure, it might "look" like that...but Nature has a way of giving us counter-intuitive results...i.e. "irrationality" is adaptive.
Interestingly, I recently heard a driver of the Thrust II rocket car describe the sensations one feels when driving over the speed of sound in a car...
What was particularly interesting is that it seems when one decelerates from the speed of sound to around 500 mph (it only takes 2 seconds)...the sensation of feels is that one is going straight down INTO the ground!!!!!
Again, this is another rubber hand result...so the chap is certain he is going into the ground (i.e. his senses are telling him this)...BUT in reality he is still travelling along the horizontal...very interesting...
You ended your chapter with:
"In chapter XX “Do We Ever Deserve to be Punished?” I briefly discuss the discovery that the universe is not after all governed by strict and exceptionless laws, but merely by probabilistic laws. So it turns out that the most that someone furnished with full information about my physical body and environment could ever predict about my future behaviour is what I will probably do"
Now, this is plain wrong, wrong, wrong....
Probability is a human information relationship with the universe...it is isn't a real thing...it simply is observational error in a measurement...
This is quite complex...and to a large degree is dependent on what "interpretation" of quantum physics one "believes".
But, since this topic concerns "consciousness"...then I'll give you a valid example of quantum theory using consciousness...
Here, we assume the wave-function itself resides only in the person observing a measurement...let's say it is the path of an electron...here the wave-function DOES NOT describe the actual path (i.e. the real path in the world of the electron)...instead the wave-function is simply a calculation tool for determining the betting odds the observer of the measurement should assign for the outcomes of FUTURE experiments to detect the electron and is no more real than the seat number on your ticket at the Oxford Playhouse...
Think of it like this...say you and I decide to toss a coin, i.e. heads or tails...now this kind of probability is what I have just described, i.e. a future uncertainty...
But, say I toss the coin and record the result...but do it in such a way that I don't let you see the result...
In this latter case, I know the answer and you don't...Now, the probability problem is quite different...it is epistemic uncertainty...in that you don't have enough information about the world to know the result that I know...
So you see, two different kinds of probabilities...and both not about the world...but instead about the relationship of an observer with the world...
I mean, the Schrodinger equation itself is a deterministic equation...i.e. it is an extremely strict task master...
Please, don't bring quantum physics down to the level of Neo-Darwinism :)
I think there exists a big problem with Jackson's thought model.
Namely, I don't think Mary's mind would in fact perceive the colour "red".
Remember, humans are neotenous...and if she has been brought up in a total black and white environment I don't believe her brain would be requesting this "red" colour from the tomato.
I mean, humans have the ability to learn a language (i.e. experience a speaking language, sign language) ...BUT if a child is not taught a language by the time it is 12 or so...it will never learn a language.
It could be similar for colour perception...and in this case the perception would rely entirely on pre-cognitive brain functions, i.e. Familiar memory...one does not "know" one sees red(i.e. ...one as a child is simply taught to see red...no reasons are ever given to the child that the tomato is red...it just is).
It is simply an objective hinge that one trusts.
So the assumption I challenge is where you say "But Mary previously knew all the physical facts". If knowledge of the physical facts consists in a complex organisation of data in the brain, which needs to be at least as complex as the physical facts themselves, and if it is impossbile to acquire such organisation by low bandwidth methods, then this crucial assumption is false.
"Jackson seems to have shown that there are more facts than just the physical facts." No. There are just the physical facts. But the physical facts in this case are themselves knowledge, i.e. brain states. So knowledge of the physical facts would be knowledge of brain states or knowledge of knowledge. But it is difficult – for purely material reasons – to have a brain state which is itself a complete representation of a brain state.
The fact that the materialist model is not working here...is a sign that it is not a good model.
Why is any of this true?
There are just as many unanswered questions about "physical reality" though I don't necessarily think consciousness is seperate from that.
If you don't know what I mean, define what energy actually is. I mean in what it actually is not vagueries about being able to do work. Energy/mass in the fundamental stuff of the universe and we don't really know what it is at bottom.
We accept all manner of odd properties of matter. There is no ultimate explanation of why any of should be so but we accept it. We privalage consciousness because it is so important to us but why not just accept it as yet one more odd property of matter in certain arrangements.
And that these physical attributes are simply intrinsic information of a real physical measurement.
If one does this then one eventually is lead to the famous equivalence relation:
(Energy)^2=(speed of light)^2*(momentum)^2+(mass)^2*(speed of light)^4
Which simply links mass, momentum and energy.
The thing is this equation defines the extensional co-ordinates of energy and momentum values without any need of a materialist world-view.
At root this is probably the reason that in all Lagrangians in physics equations...they ALL have a squared energy gradient term...and this term defines the intrinsic information of a particular problem...now, information is not a "material" thing.
In his model of evolution knowledge is adaptive...meaning essentially that "knowledge", i.e. something immaterial is a real variable in the universe.