Skip to main content

Humanism and secularism - draft chpt for comments (4.5k words)

For OUP VSI Humanism book.

What is secularism?

Humanism involves a commitment to secularism. But what is secularism?

The term “secular” is used in at least two different ways. Sometimes it means little more than “not religious”. Often, when people describe a society as becoming “more secular”, they just mean that it is becoming less religious.

However, the term “secular” also has at least one other meaning. When humanists say they want a “secular society”, they are usually advocating a particular political view about how society should be organized, a view about what the relationship should be between the state and religion.

A secular society, thus understood, is not necessarily a society in which there is little or no public manifestation of religious belief. A secular society could be one in which everyone is deeply religious, in which religious points of view are regularly publicly expressed. A secular society is one in which the state itself takes a neutral view on religion. The state does not align itself with any particular religious, or anti-religious, point of view.

A secular society, in the sense we are discussing now, protects certain freedoms. It protects the freedom of individuals to believe, or not believe, to worship, or not worship. A secular society defends the right of individuals to express religious commitments. But it also protects their right to express views critical of religion.

Characterized in this way, secularism and atheism are clearly very different things. An Islamic or Christian theocracy is obviously not secular, because one particular religion dominates the state. But then an atheist state such as Stalin’s Russia or Mao’s China cannot be described as secular either. Both these totalitarian regimes suppressed the freedom to worship and express religious views.

So a secular society is religiously neutral. That is not to say it is neutral about everything, of course. It is not neutral on the importance of protecting certain freedoms. But it is founded on principles framed and justified independently of any particular pro- or anti-religious commitment: principles to which we ought to be able to sign up whether we are religious or not.

Understood in this way, a secular society is one in which religious people can feel just as much at home as can atheists. Indeed, many religious people are political secularists. They value the kind of religious freedoms such a secular society guarantees.

Secularism is sometimes characterized by its opponents as the view we should gag religious voices in public sphere – that the state should actively work to prevent any religious opinions being heard. But that would be a caricature of what I, and indeed most people who advocate secularism, mean by the term. The British Humanist Association (BHA), for example, promotes secularism, but it does not advocate preventing people from publicly expressing religious points of view. The kind of secularism advocated by the BHA actually protects the freedom to express such views. It just denies religious voices should be given a privileged position. But then it denies atheist voices should be given a privileged position too.

Although most Westerners now take their freedom publicly to advocate or criticize religious points of view for granted, this freedom was in many cases hard won, and, across much of the Europe, has existed for only a few hundred years. In the West, the secular society is a comparatively recent phenomenon.

It is also worth remembering that many Western states are not that secular. The British state, does of course guarantee the freedom of its citizens to worship or not worship in whatever way they see fit. But it does give one religion - the Church of England - a privileged position. For example, it allocates twenty-six seats in the House of Lords to Bishops - all men, of course – who can then use their power to attempt to block legislation that has popular, democratic support, such as the bill on assisted dying. The British state also uses taxpayer’s money to fund religious schools, and insists that, subject to a few minor exemptions, in every state-funded school in England and Wales each pupil on each school day must take part in an act of collective worship, usually of a broadly Christian character.

One advantage of a secular society


Why have a secular society? One obvious reason is pragmatic. Secular societies developed in large measure because people recognized that there are dangers in allying states with religions. The histories of many modern states have been plagued by violence caused by competing religious groups trying to wrestle control of the state from each other: Catholic vs. Protestant, Sunni vs. Shia, Hindu vs. Muslim, Jew vs. Muslim. The secular state was eventually recognized as a way of reducing that kind of conflict, through all parties agreeing to live under a religiously neutral state that protected all their freedoms equally, giving favour to none. Secular states provide a framework for peaceful co-existence between religions, and have proved highly successful in this respect.

Threats to the secular state


One way in which the secular character of a society can begin to be eroded is if the religious begin to insist their particular religious views are deserving of special, institutionalized forms of privilege or respect. Here are six recent examples of such claims:

• The state should be affiliated to one particular religion.
• The state should not permit plays, publications, etc. that satirize, or might in some way deeply offend those holding, certain religious beliefs.
• Airlines and schools should not have the power to ban flight attendants or school pupils from wearing religious symbols, if the individual’s religion, or conscience, requires it.
• The state should fund religiously-affiliated schools that are permitted to discriminate against both teachers and pupils on the basis of religious belief.
• The anti-discrimination laws that apply to everyone else should not apply to, say, adoption agency workers who are Catholic and who are asked to help gay couples adopt.

In some cases, the particular privilege it is supposed religion should receive already exists.

Many people believe these claims are legitimate. Even some non-religious people have sympathy with at least some of them. But can such claims be justified?

A challenge for anti-secularists

Suppose we cross out the word “religious” in each of the above bulletpoints, and replace it with the word “political”. How plausible do you find the resulting claim?

• The state should be explicitly affiliated to one particular political party.
• The state should not permit plays, publications, etc. that satirize, or might in some way deeply offend those holding, certain political beliefs.
• Airlines and schools should not have the power to ban flight attendants or school pupils from wearing political symbols, if the individual’s political party, or conscience, requires it.
• The state should fund political-party-affiliated schools that are permitted to discriminate against both teachers and pupils on the basis of political belief.
• The anti-discrimination laws that apply to everyone else should not apply to, say, adoption agency workers belonging to a racist political party who are asked help racially-mixed couples adopt.

Most of us, including most religious people, now reject all five claims, and with good cause. There are obvious reasons why the state should not align itself with one political party, no matter how benign and well-meaning that party might be. And of course we should be permitted to satirize and mock the political beliefs of others, irrespective of the offence caused – that right is a feature of any healthy democracy.

But then the challenge facing those who make the religious versions of such claims, yet reject the political versions, is to explain why these differing attitudes to the two sets of claims is justified. Why, for example, if the state should not fund political schools discriminating on the basis of political belief, should we expect it to fund religious schools discriminating on the basis of political belief?

This challenge can be sharpened by noting that, very often, religious beliefs are political beliefs. Consider, for example religious beliefs concerning the moral status of the actively homosexual, women’s role in society, stem cell research, abortion, jihad, the State of Israel, and our moral and financial responsibilities towards the less fortunate. Such beliefs are all highly political. Indeed, religious organizations are often political active, forming powerful political lobbies. So why should the addition of a religious dimension to a set of political beliefs entail that those beliefs are then deserving of officially sanctioned privileges they would not otherwise enjoy?

Responses to the challenge


How might those who believe the State should be affiliated to a particular religion, fund religious, schools, and so on, respond to this challenge? If they are not to appear guilty of unfounded prejudice, they need to identify some difference between religious and other political beliefs that justifies this difference in treatment. Let’s look at four differences that might be supposed to provide that justification.

One very obvious difference between religious and other political beliefs is that the former typically involve reference to a supernatural agent or agents. However, this difference, by itself, surely fails explain why, say, religious beliefs should not be satirized. After all, some people believe in supernatural beings such as ghosts and fairies. Yet we don’t suppose such beliefs should not be mocked – quite the opposite. Moreover, there are some religions – such as certain versions of Buddhism – that involve no belief in supernatural agents. Should Buddhism therefore fail to qualify for the privileges or protections afforded other religions? That seems absurd.

A second difference that some may suppose justifies the state treating religious beliefs differently is that religious beliefs are often very passionately held. Indeed, people are prepared to die for their religious beliefs. Might this explain why these beliefs ought, then, to be given a special status? On closer examination, this justification also fails. Non-religious political beliefs may be just as passionately held. People are also prepared to die for them. That is true of many communists, for example. So should the state fund communist schools that discriminate against non-communist? Should the state prevent communist beliefs from being satirized or mocked?

A third difference that some suppose justifies the state treating religious beliefs differently is that they often forms part of a person's identity in a way that other beliefs - including even political beliefs - do not. People self-identify as Christian or Muslim or Jews, and often feel a strong kinship with other Christians Muslims Jews and Hindus that often transcends any differences in race, nationality and so on. Admittedly, this is by no mean true of all religions, but it is true of many. Political movements and parties, by contrast, are rarely woven into a person’s sense of who they essentially are to anything like the same extent (though under certain totalitarian regimes they may be).

There is no doubt that someone brought up to attend regular devotional events, who makes regular pilgrimages abroad, whose devotional community transcends national boundaries, whose clothing and/or jewellery reflects their deep commitment, who gives time each day to related reading, whose home is hung with related icons and portraits, and who perhaps even permanently marks their body with signs of their devotion, is someone for whom that commitment has become an integral part of their sense of who they fundamentally are. But does the identity-determining dimension to their commitment justify the state giving that commitment special treatment? Clearly not if they are committed Manchester United supporters, many of whom check all of the above boxes. But then why should a religious commitment be treated any differently?

It is true, of course that, because some religious people are so passionately committed to their faith, to the point where it has become a part of their sense of who they are, criticism or mockery of that faith is likely to be taken at a deeply personal level. As a result, they may become particularly enraged, perhaps even violent.

Those critical of religious belief, ought, then, to be careful about how they frame their criticisms. They ought not to engage in entirely pointless mockery or insult – in baiting the fervently religious just for the sake of it. Given the predictable results, that would clearly be irresponsible.

However, it does not follow that the state itself ought, then, to ban criticism or mockery of religious belief. Criticism – and also irony, parody, sarcasm and lampooning – still has its place. True, satire sometimes amounts to little more than pointless insult, but can also take the form of great art, presenting us with the truth in a particularly arresting and insightful way (think of the satires of Jonathan Swift, for example).

In any case, banning the mockery of beliefs on the grounds that those holding them are likely to become violent as a result actually encourages people to become violent whenever their beliefs are mocked. The moral drawn will be, “Get sufficiently enraged and aggressive, and the state will then prevent people mocking your beliefs too, whatever they happen to be!” All Swiftian satires will have to be outlawed, unless they happen to be targeted at the beliefs of those of us with milder tempers.

A fourth suggestion as to why religious beliefs ought to be given a special status by the State is that the rights and freedoms we enjoy in modern liberal societies grew our of, and were original justified by, reference to a religious framework and values, and that, unless there is continuing, explicit support for that framework and those values, those rights and liberties are increasingly likely to come under threat. Here, for example, is British Philosopher Prof Roger Trigg expressing this worry in his book Religion in Public Life.

As a matter of historical fact, the standards of Western Society have arisen from a Christian background… the urge to respect different beliefs, and value individual freedom, needs to be nurtured publicly, and if religious views initially produced it, there is a question how long it can survive without their explicit support. [p3-4]

Notice Trigg is not claiming that every liberal society requires a religious underpinning to survive. He is making the more modest claim that those liberal societies that originally had a religious foundation are at risk if that foundation is lost. This is a good reason for keeping the religious foundation in place. Trigg asks:

Why is freedom to be respected, and human equality cherished? These questions have a ready answer in a religious context, since God, it will be held, has made us equal, cares for us equally, and has given us free-will so as to make reasoned choices. Once the religious context is subtracted, the mere existence of rights can seem more precarious. [p73]

This is a common criticism of the modern secular society. Here, for example, is Bishop Michael Nazir Ali,

There are certain basic values to identify in British life which come from a Christian vision. For instance, the dignity of all humans beings is clearly drawn from the Biblical idea that humans beings are made in God’s image. Or it might be the question of equality, or it might be liberty, freedom of expression. All these things are under threat… Unless people know what the springs are that feed our values, the whole thing will dry up…. We may already be living on past capital, where we have some sense of values but don’t know why we have them.

Indeed, Trigg argues that, once this religious foundation is lost, there is a real risk that a society will slide into totalitarianism. It is only if there is a recognition by a state that there is something higher than it – something that can provide a check on its excesses – that the natural tendency of states to drift towards totalitarianism is kept under control.

[M]any would want to see more overt recognition by the State of the authority of God, because only this, it seems, may provide a limitation on the powers of human institutions. (p12)

[O]nce a State repudiates any religious foundation for itself, it recognizes no check on its powers beyond those it is prepared to recognize.(p 125).

So Trigg justifies for allying Western States with Christian churches on the grounds that only this provides a necessary brake on the tendency of such states to drift towards totalitarianism. The justification is ingenious. But does it hold water?

I don’t believe so. First of all, it is by no means obvious that Trigg’s recommendation is supported by the historical evidence. Just over one of my lifetimes ago, much of Europe was overrun by a totalitarian state. How did the Christian churches respond to this growing menace? In many places, church leaders welcomed the arrival of the Nazis. True, there was the occasional protest against the increasingly brutal and violent treatment of Jews. For example, in1936, the Catholic Primate of Poland issued a letter opposing violence against Jews. Here’s an extract:

It is a fact that the Jews are fighting against the Catholic Church, persisting in free-thinking, and are the vanguard of godlessness, Bolshevism and subversion. It is a fact that the Jewish influence on morality is pernicious and that their publishing houses disseminate pornography. It is a fact that Jews deceive, levy interest, and are pimps. It is a fact that the religious and ethical influence of the Jewish young people on Polish young people is a negative one.{REF}

This letter, written by the most senior Catholic in Poland, was read from the pulpit of every Polish Catholic Church in 1936. Even while opposing violence against Jews, the letter nevertheless illustrates the sort of contempt in which Jews were held by many Catholics across Europe prior to the Holocaust. The Christian churches very much contributed to the perception that the Jews were a “problem”.

The behaviour of the Catholic Church during the rise of Nazi totalitarianism in Europe was in large measure shameful. The Church signed a concordat with Hitler in 1933 protecting Church interests, such as the right to collect Church taxes, and guaranteeing the protection of Catholic organizations and freedom of religious practice and the teaching of the Catholic religion in schools. After the Nazis broke the agreement, the Church subsequently criticised the regime (most notably in the Papal encyclical Mit Brennender Sorge - “With Great Sorrow” - published in 1937). It is true that some Catholics, and perhaps even the Pope, worked to save Jewish lives, However, even after the war, many within the Catholic Church remained supportive of the Nazis. Indeed a team of Catholics working within the Vatican itself arranged for thousands of Nazis to flee Germany, even providing Adolf Eichmann, architect in chief of the Final Solution, with his fake passport and a route to safety in Argentina.

Lest it be thought I am focussing unfairly on the Catholic Church, I should stress that the established German Protestant churches were also guilty of shameful behaviour. They too had a long history of anti-semitism, and signally failed to offer any resistance to the rise of Nazism. While some prominent Protestants, such as Martin Neimoller and Dietrich Bonhoeffer, resisted the Nazis, note that they had to leave the established churches in order to do so.

But perhaps Nazi Germany was an exception? What of other totalitarian states, such as Fascist Italy? How did the Christian churches respond to the rise of totalitarianism there? Catholicism was recognised as the sole religion of state. What of the rise of fascism in Spain? How did the Catholic Church resist? It didn’t. It supported the murderous General Franco in overthrowing a democratically elected Government.

The Christian churches, do not have a good track record of resisting European totalitarianism. They have often been content to do business with, and even officially sanction and support, totalitarian regimes, at least up until the point where those regimes have started to threaten church interests. Of course, there is one exception to this tendency of Christian churches to work hand-in-glove with totalitarian states, and that is the atheistic Communist totalitarian regimes of Eastern Europe, which the Catholic Church has always worked vigorously to overthrow.

We should also remember that, just four of my lifetimes ago, the Catholic Church was itself still arranging for the garrotting by the Spanish State of citizens who failed to believe what the Church told them. The Inquisition worked hand-in-hand with the State to stifle individual freedoms, using the State as its executioner. In that instance, the Catholic Church was not so much a brake on the totalitarian tendencies of a state as a root cause of them.

The suggestion that by affiliating themselves with Christian churches is the best protection European states have against sliding into totalitarianism is not, then, particularly well-supported by the historical evidence. If anything, the warning from history is: don’t rely on the churches to protect us from totalitarianism. As often as not, the churches are part of the problem.

Of course it is important we recognise that there are principles higher than the state. Most of us, religious or not, recognise that this is true of moral principles. What the state decrees is morally right or wrong is not necessarily so. A church could be among those offering moral criticism of the state when it begins to slide in a totalitarian direction. Getting into bed with the state might increase the power and authority of a church to act as a curb on excesses of state power, but at the same time it makes it less likely that any such criticism will be offered. Once church and state have entered into an arrangement of mutual support, each then has a vested interest in protecting the power and authority of the other. Surely a church is most likely to offer such criticism when it is genuinely independent of the State, rather than working hand-in-glove with it.

What of Trigg’s suggestion that our modern liberal values have a religious foundation without which they are likely to be eroded? While it is true that our modern political rights and freedoms were originally often justified in religious terms, that is because, back then, every moral and political position tended to be justified in religious terms. As the authors of the British Humanist Association’s pamphlet The Case For Secularism point out,

Christianity has been the dominant culture, so it is unsurprising that it has supplied the vocabulary of both sides in most significant moral and social divisions. Those who worked for the abolition of the slave trade argued their case in terms of Christian values – and so did the slave-traders. Many of those who sought to improve the atrocious working conditions in factories and mines invoked Christian values – and so did the factory owners and mine owners. Some at least of those who campaigned for greater equality of opportunity, for the extension of the franchise, or for the emancipation of women, or an end to racial discrimination, invoked Christian values, and so did those who defended what they saw as a divinely ordained and unchangeable hierarchy of status and inequality. (p4-5)

Even if, as a matter of historical fact, our modern liberal values were originally argued for on religious grounds, moral and political philosophers have developed a whole range of justifications on which we can also draw, including the pragmatic justification outlined earlier. There is no necessity that our rights and freedoms be justified on religious grounds.

Of course, critics of secularism may insist that these other non-religious justifications just don’t work. However, justifications based on the assumption that the Judeo-Christian God exists look even less credible to the majority of political theorists and philosophers (indeed, a recent poll indicates that only 14.6% of professional philosophers believe in a god or gods).

Moreover, in a country such as the U.K. where a significant and growing number of citizens – a third - are not even Christian, the result of giving our core values a specifically Christian justification is that those values are then more, not less, likely to be ignored or rejected by a significant number of citizens. Surely, if we want everyone to sign up to certain core values, such as human rights, wouldn’t it better if a religiously-neutral justification of those rights were offered instead?

Conclusion


Many, though by no mean all, religious people suppose that, when an airline is permitted to instruct staff not to wear religious symbols, or when Catholic staff of adoption agencies are compelled to offer gay couples the same service they offer others, this constitutes a form of unfair discrimination against those with strong religious convictions. The religious are being unfairly victimized. We are not showing their beliefs proper “respect”. But this is not obviously the case. Not if airlines are similarly permitted to ban staff from wearing (other) political symbols. Not if racist staff of adoption agencies are compelled to offer mixed race couples the same service they offer others. Why should airlines treat religious symbols differently to other political symbols? And, if we don’t allow non-religiously motivated bigots to discriminate unfairly against others, why should we treat religiously motivated bigots any differently?

I have anticipated four possible answers to the question “Why should the state accord religious beliefs privileges it does not extend to other beliefs – such as purely political beliefs?’ None of the answers examined has proved adequate. However, many other answers might be given. This brief overview is designed to illustrate the point that, while it may strike many of us as “just obvious” that religious beliefs do deserve such special treatment, some of the more obvious justifications that might be given for privileging religious belief fail. Indeed, I have yet to find any adequate justification for assigning religious beliefs such a privileged status.

Comments

Paul P. Mealing said…
Hi Stephen.

I live in a secular, pluralist society, that I like to think has been very successful, and, whilst I agree with much of your argument, there is one point where I disagree with you strongly.

Airlines and schools should not have the power to ban flight attendants or school pupils from wearing religious symbols, if the individual’s religion, or conscience, requires it.

I actually concur with that statement.

Some political conservatives in Australia (one in particular) wanted us to follow the French example and ban religious symbols in schools (specifically the hijab). Fortunately, common sense has prevailed, thus far, and everyone else agrees it would be a truly stupid idea and create a problem where none currently exists.

I disagree that religious symbols are analogous to political symbols, because they are about cultural identity, not political affiliation. All my adult life I’ve been against the deliberate stifling of identity, or the homogenisation of identity, if I can coin a phrase, even amongst children.

I think banning religious symbols on airline attendants is petty and for school children would be inflammatory. I’m all for people expressing their identity and being proud to do so. The banning of the wearing of religious symbols is provocative and possibly anti-democratic in my view. Religion is not politics, but a good way to make it political is to start banning the expression of individual religious identity.

Regards, Paul.
Unknown said…
Stephen:

Some random thoughts provoked by your well-written article--

"Humanism involves a commitment to secularism," and by secularism you mean a political relationship where the state protects the individual's freedom to believe or not believe, to worship or not worship. But I think one could be a Christian humanist, for instance, or a Muslim humanist, and yet still be committed to the protection of these individual rights for all members of society.

In other words, every religious tradition has elements that support pluralism and tolerance, along with elements that tend toward exclusivism and intolerance.

Another thought: the term "religion" is a pejorative term applied by many rationalists and humanists to distance themselves from world views that are not their own. In this sense, religion is something that means the opposite of science, reason, and naturalism.

In contrast, I think that everyone has a world view, meaning ways of being and thinking that lie behind one's hopes, fears, actions, reactions, ideas, plans, ways of thinking, methods of validation, and explanations for what life is, why things happen, how we happen to be here, and where our destiny lies. What I've just written is a rational humanist way of putting it. A traditional Christian could put it in Christian language, a Buddhist in Buddhist terms, and so on.

In this sense, we either drop the term "religion" and talk about "totalizing worldviews," or keep the word "religion" and call rationalist-humanist-secularism a "religion." I prefer the former.

I prefer to see the matter of "the relationship between the state and religion" as the matter of totalizing worldviews that are contesting for power, that are seeking legitimacy among the people by appealing to various sources of authority.

It happens that I prefer to live under any totalizing worldview that protects individual and community freedoms to believe or not, to worship or not, to criticize or not, to be supernaturalist or not, and to follow traditions or not. But for any such totalizing worldview to be in power means that it must use the coercive force of the state against any totalizing worldview that would oppose it.
Unknown said…
typo: "religious voices in public sphere" should be "religious voices in the public sphere"
wombat said…
Paul

"Airlines and schools should not have the power to ban flight attendants or school pupils from wearing religious symbols, if the individual’s religion, or conscience, requires it."

But we recognize that the airline must be free to prohibit clothing etc which contravenes safety regulations and should also be free to enforce a dress code which carries its corporate identity. We certainly allow it to do so in respect of other cultural identities. Would you expect an airline to allow a naturist to carry out their duties unclothed or a hippy to wear a headband with "Legalize dope" written on it? That being said it must be an even handed policy and not subject to whims of line managers with prejudices.
Unknown said…
In "if the individual’s religion, or conscience, requires it" I would put "conscience" in quotes. Religion and conscience are not the same thing.
Unknown said…
typo: "often political active" should be "often politically active".
Unknown said…
typo: in "fund religious, schools", delete the comma
Martin said…
Ireland has taken a step away from secularism leading to Atheist Ireland publishing 25 Blasphemous Quotes.

Speaking as an atheist and a secularist I can see a couple of conundrums you have failed to untangle in your piece.

The banning of religious symbols would necessarily include the banning of the Muslim hijab and the Sikh turban. However, I am not offended if people dress this way, and similarly not offended if a Christian wears a cross. In fact I am offended by the act of banning of such things. Modern theories about discrimination suggest that discrimination occurs if a person feels discriminated against, not just if the discriminator deliberately discriminates. So a Christian IS discriminated against if the have remove their cross, no matter whether the rule is universal or not. You and I know that Jesus was a Jew with a political message, so that in some circumstances a political symbol can become conflated with a religious one. But it still seems a step too far for airline employees to wear overtly political symbols. Could they, however, wear a badge to indicate they were a member of a Trade Union? It seems that somewhere an arbitrary line has to be drawn.

Secondly, one of the insidious acts of the Nazi regime was to insist that Jews wore a Star of David on their arm. In this case it was the enforced wearing of a religious symbol that was offensive. A secular state should be ensuring that people only need wear a symbol of their religion if it is their choice. Your piece does not indicate that over zealous use of religious symbols can lead to persecution, yet some of the worst crimes of the 20th century were effected in that way. By your definition it would not be discriminatory if the entire UK population had to wear a symbol of the Islamic faith, merely because we would all be forced to do the same, yet this clearly would be offensive to the vast majority of the population.
Mike said…
I too found myself pausing at the bulleted statement about airlines and schools -- not because I disagree with you, but because it is a much thornier issue than the other five (not six, as you write) statements, which all point to conclusions that seem self-evident by comparison.
Tony Lloyd said…
One advantage of a secular society

“Secular states provide a framework for peaceful co-existence between religions, and have proved highly successful in this respect.” This seems to read as if one of the points of secularism is religion: to allow religions to peacefully co-exist. This type of argument is often used by the profoundly anti-secular in the USA who claim the establishment clause is there to provide “freedom of religion not freedom from religion” and, thus, allows rampant discrimination against atheists. Could you stick “different beliefs” in there instead of “religions”?

Threats to the secular state
On the religious symbols at schools and airline check-ins, might it not be worth pointing out that the schools banned all jewellery? It makes it clearer that the religious are claiming special privileges. Perhaps: “Schools should not have the power to ban jewellery if that prevents pupils from wearing religious symbols”




There is a fourth difference, or counter-counter-argument to the first. In the debate “Atheism is the new fundamentalism” a questioner put forward the idea that as Dawkins’ could not be certain of God’s non-existence Dawkins should not hold the belief that God does not exist. Dawkins reply included the argument that we cannot be certain that leprechauns do not exist, yet most sane people hold the belief that they do not exist. Richard Harries reacted angrily to this argument, calling it a “ridiculous remark” as it confused the “God of Classical Theism which has animated the whole of Western Philosophy with a leprechaun”. (This is around 4:30 to 7:50 in “Chapter Six” of the debate on the Intelligence Squared website).
Harries’ counter-argument is incomplete and I’ve been pondering what the missing premise is. I think it’s a conservative presumption of respect for a belief that has stood the test of time mingled with the idea that a body of belief has rights: theism is obviously sensible because so many people believe it and it’s just nasty to have a go at something that’s given you Descartes’ “Meditations”. I think this is different from Trigg’s argument (although it sounds similar) in that Trigg’s is causal, theism does X, whereas Harries’ is ethical/epistemological.

“A third difference that some suppose…they often forms” mix of singular and plural

“Identity”: would race be a better example?

I don’t think the ability of religion to criticise State morals is any argument in favour of privileging religion at all: the ability to criticise is guaranteed by secularism.

I don’t think the discussion of the foundation of public morals on religion works. “Even if, as a matter of historical fact, our modern liberal values were originally argued for on religious grounds”. Haven’t you just shown that they were not, at least, founded on religious grounds? As religion determines “either slavery or manumission” it neither determines slavery nor manumission. So those arguing against (or for) slavery drew their opinions from outside religion. There is no need to provide an alternative to religious justification where religion does not provide a justification.
anticant said…
The Biblical Jehovah and his followers throughout history would have been a whole heap nicer if he were a leprechaun! Leprechauns have a sense of fun (so I'm told).
Mike said…
Trigg's argument is positively medieval. It evokes that time in Europe when the church was a powerful counterforce to the otherwise absolute monarchs who could rule by arbitrary decree. In making this argument he demonstrates that his thinking has not even made it as far as the Enlightenment, let alone the 21st century. Your point that the churches not only acquiesced, but actually colluded with the rise of totalitarian states in fascist Spain, Germany and Italy is well taken. Judging from the historical record it seems religious authorities will oppose anti-democratic governments only when those governments (like the Soviets) oppose them.
wombat said…
Triggs assertion that states need to acknowledge a "higher power" seems to run in to the difficulty that a church of some sort is required to intermediate in some way and in effect becomes the ultimate authority in the absence of direct supernatural intervention or unambiguous scripture. Simply saying that one has regard for the higher authority does not make it tangible. One might point to non-theocratic dictatorships that have helped themselves to this by invoking "the people" as this higher power and taking such titles as "chairman".
Cathy Davis said…
Humanism is something internal to a being, while secularism is what we try to play in the outside world.
hank_says said…
Thanks Stephen, nicely done. I've written about the dangers of theocracy myself (http://generalsystemsvehicle.blogspot.com/2009/09/on-church-and-state.html) and it's great to see some work written from the other side of the glass. I really wish more anti-secularists would make an effort to understand that secularism is on their side and is probably their best friend, politically - but that'd be like attempting to get creationists to understand evolution.

Paul (first commenter), as a fellow Aussie I concur - banning religious jewellery or clothing would be needlessly inflammatory and completely against secular principles. Ban undeserved privilege, yes. Ban headscarves (not to be confused with full-concealment burqas)? Ridiculous. You'd have to go the whole hog and institute similar hat-bans for orthodox Jews in Caulfield for such a thing to have any credibility.
Unknown said…
Visit


http://www.badscience.net/forum/viewtopic.php?f=3&t=13976&start=0


to see how this so-called *NEW ATHEISM* has been completely crushed


Atheist:

have you for but a moment considered that you have adopted a position against 98% of the human race, both past and present?

do you think you are RIGHT and they are all WRONG?

WRONG




now listen to this arrogant puffed up son of a bitch....

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ilWM7jIEN_k


little scientist geek who would try to usurp God Himself!!!


the atheist sins not only against God, but also against man...
Mike said…
wombat,
Yes -- In the Middle ages it was politically necessary for kings to claim that their right to rule was derived from God, so the Church could use its leverage as a mediator, so to speak. But in a democracy, between whom would the unelected church leaders mediate? Between the people and their own elected legislators or their own elected executive? It's absurd.
wombat said…
Mike -
Absurd it may be but I think its pretty much the pattern in Iran - there is an elected element (not going to debate the legitimacy of it here) but there is also an element of religious oversight not just in the fact that a candidate may be vetoed by the clergy which is really a political power, but that rulings may be delivered by the clergy regarding acceptability of laws on religious grounds.
hank_says said…
Strangelove - it doesn't matter that 98% of the human race is religious now or has been religious in the past. It doesn't even matter if your 98% figure is even accurate. The fact remains that today there is as much evidence to support religion as there has ever been. Can you guess the quantity I'm thinking of?

Now, think about all the religions that have ever existed and think about why you don't believe any of them. Atheists just go one god further than you do - and there certainly isn't anything new about it! When you understand why you don't worship Zeus, hopefully you'll understand why atheists don't believe in ANY god.
Mike said…
Good point about Iran, wombat. Not exactly a model democracy.

Popular posts from this blog

EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS

(Published in Faith and Philosophy 2011. Volume 28, Issue 2, April 2011. Stephen Law. Pages 129-151) EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS Stephen Law Abstract The vast majority of Biblical historians believe there is evidence sufficient to place Jesus’ existence beyond reasonable doubt. Many believe the New Testament documents alone suffice firmly to establish Jesus as an actual, historical figure. I question these views. In particular, I argue (i) that the three most popular criteria by which various non-miraculous New Testament claims made about Jesus are supposedly corroborated are not sufficient, either singly or jointly, to place his existence beyond reasonable doubt, and (ii) that a prima facie plausible principle concerning how evidence should be assessed – a principle I call the contamination principle – entails that, given the large proportion of uncorroborated miracle claims made about Jesus in the New Testament documents, we should, in the absence of indepen...

Aquinas on homosexuality

Thought I would try a bit of a draft out on the blog, for feedback. All comments gratefully received. No doubt I've got at least some details wrong re the Catholic Church's position... AQUINAS AND SEXUAL ETHICS Aquinas’s thinking remains hugely influential within the Catholic Church. In particular, his ideas concerning sexual ethics still heavily shape Church teaching. It is on these ideas that we focus here. In particular, I will look at Aquinas’s justification for morally condemning homosexual acts. When homosexuality is judged to be morally wrong, the justification offered is often that homosexuality is, in some sense, “unnatural”. Aquinas develops a sophisticated version of this sort of argument. The roots of the argument lie in thinking of Aristotle, whom Aquinas believes to be scientifically authoritative. Indeed, one of Aquinas’s over-arching aims was to show how Aristotle’s philosophical system is broadly compatible with Christian thought. I begin with a sketch of Arist...

The Evil God Challenge and the "classical" theist's response

On another blog, FideCogitActio, some theists of a "classical" stripe (that's to say, like Brian Davies, Edward Feser) are criticisng the Evil God Challenge (or I suppose, trying to show how it can be met, or sidestepped). The main post includes this: In book I, chapter 39 , Aquinas argues that “there cannot be evil in God” (in Deo non potest esse malum). Atheists like Law must face the fact that, if the words are to retain any sense, “God” simply cannot be “evil”. As my comments in the thread at Feser’s blog aimed to show, despite how much he mocks “the privation theory of evil,” Law himself cannot escape its logic: his entire argument requires that the world ought to appear less evil if it is to be taken as evidence of a good God. Even though he spurns the idea that evil is a privation of good, his account of an evil world is parasitic on a good ideal; this is no surprise, though, since all evil is parasitic on good ( SCG I, 11 ). Based on the conclusions of se...