Skip to main content

Israel, Palestine and Terror


(reposting)

Jerry Cohen's chapter from my book Israel, Palestine and Terror is available on-line here. I think it's one of the strongest pieces in the book. My own contribution (three thousand words) is pasted in below.

Terror in Palestine: A Non-Violent Alternative?

Stephen Law

In this volume, the philosophers Ted Honderich and Tomis Kapitan argue that Palestinians have a moral right to use terrorism. Honderich’s and Kapitan’s arguments differ. For example, Honderich’s is rooted in his Principle of Humanity, while Kapitan develops a justification within something like the framework of ‘just war theory’. Nevertheless, both arguments conclude that Palestinian terrorism has been justified in at least some instances. And both rest on a key premise: that the Palestinians have had available to them no viable alternative to the use of terrorism. Honderich writes:

that the Palestinians' only means to a viable state has been and may still be terrorism is something about which I myself have no doubt. Evidently it is a factual proposition in need of support. There is enough in the history of Palestine and Israel to lead me to think that the disinterested people who say the Palestinians had and have an alternative to terrorism are less moved by history and fact than by abhorrence for terrorism. The feeling cannot settle the question (Honderich 2008, xx).

Kapitan argues that non-violent methods are unlikely to end the existential threat he believes the Palestinian community faces. He says,

[t]he Palestinians have repeatedly used techniques of non-violence in combating the Israeli occupation… and have sought and received the help of like-minded Israelis, but to no avail. (Kapitan 2008, xx)

Here I raise a question mark over this denial that there is an effective, non-violent alternative to terror open to the Palestinian people.


What is non-violent resistance?

Most non-violent resistance falls under one of three broad headings:

Acts of protest and persuasion. These include vigils, public meetings, marches and demonstrations. Protesters may wear badges, put up posters, place flowers in guns.

Non-cooperation. Citizens may refuse to cooperate socially, politically and economically. They may boycott sporting events, refuse to pay taxes or carry identity cards. They may refuse to work, or, if they are in the armed forces, to fight.

No-violent intervention. This includes actions designed to frustrate the activities and institutions deemed to be unjust. They include sit-ins, occupations and blockades.

These are just a few illustrations. There is a huge range of non-violent techniques protestors can apply. For those interested, Gene Sharp, an academic and leading advocate of non-violence, has listed one hundred and ninety-eight non-violent techniques. (The list is available at http://www.peacemagazine.org/198.htm.)

How does no-violent resistance work? There are two main mechanisms. First, non-violent resistance can frustrate the activities and institutions of the oppressor, making it difficult or even impossible for that oppression to continue.

Some proponents of non-violence, such as Sharp (1980), take as their starting point the idea that the political power of a state is derived from its subjects. If a people refuse to obey, its leaders are rendered powerless.

Certainly, massive, non-violent action can make a people ungovernable. When an incredulous British Brigadier asked Gandhi whether he expected the British simply to ‘walk out’ of India, Gandhi replied,

In the end, you will walk out. For you will come to realize that 100,000 British cannot control 500 million Indians if they choose not to obey.

There was, indeed, an inevitability about the success of India’s non-violent struggle. However, when those engaged in non-violent resistance form a less overwhelming majority, success is no longer guaranteed.

A second way in which non-violence can be effective is by changing attitudes. It can raise awareness and highlight injustice. It can also harness the power of shame.

Even when non-violent protest fails to shift the views of the oppressor, it may still succeed in persuading a wider audience that the protestor’s cause is just and that it should be supported. As a result of non-violent action by an oppressed people, international pressure may be brought to bear on their behalf.

Non-violence can work

Non-violence can work. We know that Gandhi and his followers succeeded in releasing India from the grip of the British by wholly non-violent means, and that Martin Luther King’s advocacy of non-violent protest was pivotal in establishing greater justice for black people in the U.S. Non-violence has been used with effect around the world, including in the former Eastern Bloc, in South Africa, and in the Philippines, where ‘people power’ toppled the Marcos dictatorship.

Indeed, proponents of non-violence suggest the world has been shaped far more by non-violent action than most of us imagine. The non-violence proponent Walter Wink claims that

In 1989, thirteen nations comprising 1,695,000,000 people experienced nonviolent revolutions that succeeded beyond anyone's wildest expectations ... If we add all the countries touched by major nonviolent actions in our century (the Philippines, South Africa ... the independence movement in India ...) the figure reaches 3,337,400,000, a staggering 65% of humanity! All this in the teeth of the assertion, endlessly repeated, that nonviolence doesn't work in the 'real' world.

Still, even if Wink is correct about the impressive track record of non-violent methods, there’s little doubt that such techniques can and do fail. The non-violent resistance of the Tibetans to Chinese occupation was met with devastating brutality, as were the non-violent protests in Tiananmen Square.

Factors impacting on the effectiveness of non-violent action

Common sense suggests factors likely to enhance the effectiveness of non-violent action include the following:

(1) Commitment on a massive scale. Where non-violent techniques are applied sporadically and half-heartedly, they are unlikely to succeed.
(2) A clearly stated aim. Widespread nonviolence is less likely to achieve an aim if that aim is amorphous. Actions that merely give protestors an opportunity to express their displeasure at the current situation are less likely to be effective than those that state, consistently and unambiguously, a desired alternative.
(3) Organization, strategy and leadership. Non-violent action undertaken on a massive scale may be more effective if governed by a consistent, overarching strategy to which all are committed. In addition, a charismatic and inspiring figurehead can be a great asset to such a movement, particularly after it has inevitably experienced some initial frustration, when doubts about the non-violent strategy may otherwise begin to set in.
(4) A publicly avowed commitment to pursue exclusively non-violent methods. In the absence of such a commitment, the absence of violence may be viewed by the oppressor, and any wider audience, as a largely accidental, and perhaps temporary, feature of the struggle. An explicit, principled commitment to wholly non-violent means is likely to enhance the moral authority of protestors.

Gandhi’s and Martin Luther King’s movements strongly checked all four of these boxes.

Non-violence in the first intifada

Kapitan and Honderich maintain that the Palestinians have tried non-violent techniques and that they have largely failed.

Non-violence has certainly been tried. The first intifida began in 1987 as a spontaneous, grass roots uprising. It was triggered by an incident in which an Israeli trailer crashed into two Palestinian vans, killing four and injuring ten. There was suspicion among Palestinians that, far from being an accident, this was a deliberate, vengeful attack. At the funeral, hundreds demonstrated. Israeli soldiers shot another Palestinian youth dead. The intifada developed momentum, becoming a massive, popular uprising lasting until 1993. The first intifada was largely characterized by protest and civil disobedience, though there was some violence too (much of it non-lethal, e.g. throwing stones at tanks). Here I pick out three noteworthy episodes relating to non-violent action (my main source here is Holmes 1995).

Awad

Mubarrak Awad, a Christian Arab, born in Palestine and educated in the U.S., founded the Palestinian Centre for Non-Violence in Jerusalem in 1985. Awad advocated non-violent civil disobedience. His methods were embraced and recommended by the intifada leadership that emerged. Even before the intifada, the Israeli authorities perceived Awad to be a threat to their control of the occupied territories. As Holmes notes,

The Christian Science Monitor reported on 24 November 1987 that ‘Many Israelis concede that a Gandhi-style campaign by Palestinians in the occupied territories would have a devastating effect on Israel’s ability to control those areas.’ It quoted one Israeli as saying, ‘If the Palestinians all start doing what Awad proposes, the occupation will crumble in three days.’(Holmes 1995, 212-3)

Awad himself writes (with Kuttab):

The Israelis know how to fight against an armed antagonist, but have no understanding of how to deal with non-violent resistance. They expect, and need, the Palestinians to be either submissive or violent. A non-violent approach would neutralize much of Israel’s military might. (Kuttab and Awad)

After the beginning of the intifada, Israeli efforts to remove Awad intensified and he was deported in 1988.

Beit Sahour

The town of Beit Sahour, a small, largely Christian town of about 12,000, became an early symbol of early, non-violent resistance to the occupation. It began to organize itself so as to be less reliant on Israel. An agricultural committee was created and every home developed its own vegetable garden. As Holmes notes, (1995, 213) Jud Issac, a professor and former chairman of the biology department at Bethlehem University, was jailed without charge for five months for encouraging the planting of the gardens. These ‘intifada gardens’, and the boycotting of Israeli produce, was followed by the refusal of many inhabitants to pay taxes (intifada leaders had insisted ‘no taxation without representation’). The Israeli military imposed a curfew on the town, blocked food shipments, cut telephone lines and eventually seized property from 350 inhabitants to auction off in Tel Aviv. The inhabitants still refused to pay their taxes. The Israeli blockade was lifted after six weeks, shortly before 120 members of The American Friends of Beit Sahour were scheduled to arrive to show their solidarity. In 1990, the town was awarded the annual Danish Peace Foundation prize for its commitment to non-violent methods of resistance

The ship of return

In 1988 the Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO) organized a ‘ship of return’. A vessel was purchased to take 130 Palestinian leaders expelled by Israel, along with journalists, peace activists, jurists and politicians, from Cyprus to Israel. The ship never left Cyprus. It was mined while still in harbour. The three Palestinians who had organized this non-violent action were assassinated. While Israel denied responsibility, its transport minister warned that, were another ‘ship of return’ organized, it would meet the same fate.

Further examples

Palestinians, and supporters of the Palestinian people, have engaged, and continue to engage, in non-violent resistance on a daily basis. A few more examples will give a flavour.

Palestinians adopted, and operated in accordance with, their own time zone, one hour different from Israel’s. Palestinians reported that Israeli soldiers would ask them the time, and, if Palestinian time was given, would then smash the Palestinians’ watches.

Activists in the Grassroots International protection for the Palestinians People (GIPP) have, at their own expense, made visits to the occupied territories, planting olive trees, attending lectures and demonstrating. In Ramallah, an entirely peaceful demonstration involving thousands of Palestinians and 400 foreign GIPP delegates was fired on with tear gas, sound bombs, and rubber-coated steel bullets.

Other foreign activists have received still rougher treatment. In 2003, 23 year old Rachel Corrie, a volunteer with the International Solidarity Movement, was run over by an Israeli soldier and his commander in a nine ton Caterpillar bulldozer while she stood - unarmed, and highly visible in an orange fluorescent jacket - protecting the home of a Palestinian physician slated for demolition by the Israeli army.

We should remember, too, that the Palestinians have also received support from Jews both in and outside of Israel. After the beginning of the first intifada, thirty Israeli-based organizations protested against the violent repression of the uprising. There were public rallies and acts of civil disobedience by Jews in Israel. By June 1988 more than 500 Israeli military reservists had signed a petition refusing to serve in the occupied territories.

Given that non-violent action has always been part and parcel of Palestinian resistance, given this non-violent resistance has often been dealt with brutally (as illustrated above), and given that no viable Palestinian state has been forthcoming, are we justified in concluding that non-violent methods are unlikely to achieve that aim?

Some reasons why non-violence may have failed, but might still work

I’m not sure we are justified. After all, both Honderich and Kapitan believe violent methods – including terrorism – may well work. Yet violence has also repeatedly been tried, with little success (I don’t deny that, like non-violence, it has had some limited success). Given the rather poor track record of both violent and non-violent methods, why conclude that while non-violence is unlikely to work, violence probably will?

In fact, given what has already been said regarding the effectiveness of non-violent action, there are a number of possible explanations available for why non-violence has not worked up till now, but might yet work in future. Here are a few.

1. Violence

First, while Palestinians have engaged in a great deal of non-violent action, it has always been accompanied by violence. During the first intifada, while 1100 Palestinians were killed by Israeli soldiers, 160 Israelis also died. Violence and sensational images of violence are typically of far more interest to news media than is non-violence. For this and other reasons, Palestinian violence has succeeded in largely obliterating from the minds of Americans – a key audience – any awareness of the non-violent action that has taken place. In the minds of many U.S. citizens, the word ‘intifada’ conjures up an image of a masked youth wielding a slingshot or Molotov cocktail, or more recently, wearing an explosive vest. Palestinian violence also allows Israel to view itself, and present itself to the outside world, as the victim, not the oppressor. As a result, Palestinian violence has neutralized much of the effectiveness of their non-violent action.

2. Lack of a consistent, clearly-stated aim

Second, Palestinian non-violent action has not been accompanied by an agreed, clear, consistently-stated aim or strategy. What, exactly, do the Palestinian people want? A state, yes. But on what territory, precisely? And under what conditions? In the absence of a clear and consistent answer, the answer ‘The destruction of the state of Israel’ is likely to be supplied for them (by both Arabs and Jews). At which point their cause is doomed.

3. Lack of organization and strategy

Third, while organizational structures have emerged, non-violent resistance is not nearly as well-organized as it might be. Awad and Kuttab believe that the lack of organization is at least in part down to a lack of sufficient commitment to non-violence on the Palestinian side:

There continues to be great interest in non-violence. What is lacking is an overall strategy and commitment to do it on a massive scale (Kuttab and Awad)

Moreover, those key, well-respected and charismatic Palestinian figureheads – the Palestinian Gandhis, if you like – who might have kept Palestinians on the non-violent path have been removed. Stephan writes that by 1990, Palestinian commitment to non-violent resistance was crumbling. Why? Because

Israel’s policy of arresting, detaining, and deporting… moderate Palestinian leaders effectively removed those Palestinians whose presence and leadership were needed to maintain nonviolent discipline. (Stephan 2006, 69)

4. Lack of explicit commitment to non-violence

Fourth, Palestinians have rarely explicitly committed themselves to non-violent methods. As a result, to the extent that it is even noticed at all, non-violence is widely perceived to be a merely accidental feature of their resistance. This has further eroded its effectiveness.

So yes, non-violent action has not proved particularly effective in Palestine. But there are several plausible explanations why. Were a different approach adopted – an approach combining a total absence of violence, a massive, well-organized commitment to non-violent action, an explicit renunciation of violence, and a clear, consistently stated aim – it might, perhaps, prove more effective.

Conclusion

Let’s now return to the question: is there, and has there been, a non-violent alternative open to the Palestinians? I am not entirely confident I know the answer. I am fairly confident, however, that an affirmative answer has not yet been ruled out. It seems to me that, at the very least, one premise of Honderich’s and Kapitan’s arguments – that non-violent methods cannot, or are unlikely to, work here – requires more support (certainly, more support than they provide in their contributions to this volume).

But, to be fair to Honderich and Kapitan, perhaps we need to distinguish two questions. Here’s the first. If the Palestinian people were, collectively, to engage in such non-violent action, would they succeed?

I suspect the answer to this question is – quite possibly.

But a second question is also relevant. Perhaps Honderich and Kapitan might concede that such a wholly non-violent movement could well be effective, yet still consistently argue that the individual Palestinian may yet be justified in resorting to violence and terror.

Here’s that second question. How likely is it, now, that any such wholly non-violent mass movement could actually form, given the ever-worsening political situation, the growing levels of hatred, fear and distrust among Palestinians, the manner in which their non-violent protest has been received in the past, and so on?

Suppose the answer to this question is: very unlikely indeed. While such a mass-action might succeed, it’s utterly unrealistic to expect it ever to happen.

The suggestion, then, might be this: that an individual Palestinian might justifiably conclude that, given that the Palestinian people are collectively now highly unlikely ever to engage in such action, they, as an individual, are morally within their rights to join the ranks of the violent, violence now being the only viable and effective alternative.

The upshot of such an argument might even be the seemingly paradoxical conclusion that while the Palestinian people are not collectively justified in resorting to violence or even terror (there being a viable alternative open to them collectively), they are individually.

Whether this suggestion might be developed and made to work is not a question I’ll pursue here (though I very much have my doubts).

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Holmes, R. (1995) ‘Non-Violence and the Intifada’. In Bove, L. and Kaplan L. (eds.) From The Eye of The Storm. Amsterdam – Atlanta: Rodopi. 209-222.

Honderich, T. (2008), ‘Terrorisms in Palestine’. This volume.

Kapitan, T. (2008), ‘Terror’. This volume.

Kuttab, J. and Awad, M. (undated) ‘Non-violent Resistance in Palestine: Pursuing Alternative Strategies’. Available at http://www.palestinecenter.org/cpap/pubs/20020329ib.html.

Sharp, G. (1980), Politics of Non-violent Action. Boston, Mass.: P. Sargent.

Stephan, M. (2006), ‘Fighting for Statehood: The Role of Civilian-Based Resistance in the East Timorese, Palestinian, and Kosovo Albanian Self-Determination Movements’. Forum vol 30:2. 57-79. Available at www.nonviolent-conflict.org/ PDF/Fletcher_Forum_MStephan.pdf.

Comments

S Johnson said…
In economic terms, the UK lost WWII. The effectiveness of Gandhi's nonviolence was based upon the weakness imposed on the "British" Empire by that massive violence.

What reason is there for attributing responsibility for desegregation etc. to Martin Luther King's nonviolent movement?
Competition with Communism and its criticisms of US racism was a major factor in the reforms, for instance, but the Cold War is the opposite of non-violence.
Nick said…
I haven't read Honderich's piece, so I might be doing him a disservice here if he makes other arguments. However, as quoted, his argument for the legitimacy of at least some Palestinian terrorism is far from having been shown to be sound. It seems to boil down to the following:

P1) If the Palestinians' only means to a viable state has been and may still be terrorism, then such terrorism is probably morally justified
P2) The Palestinians' only means to a viable state has been and may still be terrorism
C) Therefore, such terrorism is probably morally justified

Now, proposition P2 is not self-evidently true, and is certainly open to dispute. One can make a good case that terrorist action of this sort is likely to be ineffective and probably counter-productive in the pursuit of the goal of a viable state, and far less likely to succeed in this regard than a combination of various sorts of non-violent action, negotiation, and diplomacy (as you discuss). The latter might have little chance of success either, but it might still have more chance of success than terrorism.

However, proposition P1 is also very problematical. It too is not self-evidently true, and has not been proven to be so (unless Honderich does this elsewhere). Moreover, it rests upon an implicit generalisation of the following sort:

If we believe that the use of indiscriminate violence against innocent people is the only way to achieve some desired end, then we are probably morally justified in using such violence.

However, not only is this generalisation not shown to be true, but I think that it is most probably false. For example, as a counterexample, imagine that I desire a million pounds from my local bank, and know that the only way that I will get this money is to rob the bank, using indiscriminate violence against innocent bank employees and customers. Would I then be morally justified in doing this? Hardly.

Of course, it can be argued that the Palestinians’ case for having a viable state is a morally justified one (and, in fact, I would probably agree with that, and believe that a two state solution is probably the only feasible solution). However, imagine that the million pounds that I want from the bank is actually my money that the bank is illegitimately withholding from me. Would I then be morally justified in using indiscriminate violence against innocents in order to get my money back? I doubt it.

It might just be possible to construct a persuasive argument whereby one would be morally justified in using indiscriminate violence against innocents (with all of the moral harm that entails) in order to achieve some end when it is undeniable (to objective and dispassionate observers) that (natural) justice entails that one is entitled to that end, and where not achieving that end would be a matter of life and death (or, at minimum, where not having that end would make life utterly unbearable for any rational human in those circumstances). However, even if such an argument could be constructed in general, it is far from evident that the necessary conditions are met in the particular case of Palestine i.e. that it is undeniable (to objective and dispassionate observers) that (natural) justice entails that Palestinians are entitled to a viable state; and, more especially, that having one is a matter of life or death for them (or makes life utterly unbearable for any rational human in those circumstances).
Anonymous said…
Terrorism was a definite factor in Northern Ireland. While the same result might have been achievable through exclusively non-violent means, we can't say that for sure. It is very easy for us to sit about worrying over exactly how justified X or Y is in Palestine while we are safe and comfortable. You subject people to the conditions that the Palestinians endure; you are moronic if you think they won't attack you any way they can.

If Israel had been a nation founded on stolen land by any group other than the Jews, there would be no moral quibbling at all. It is a unique situation and while there is no question that the Jewish people suffered horrendously in Europe, it still doesn't justify the taking of Palestinian homes from their rightful owners and turning what land they have left into a prison.

Try to imagine for a second that Iran invades Ireland and treats the Irish people exactly how the Israelis treat the Palestinians.
The Irish fight back by whatever means they have available and are labelled terrorists. Iraq refuses to allow any international sanctions against Iran and supports it in the international “war on terror”. Those despicable Irish should either attack the military (equivalent to lining themselves up against the wall for ease of execution) or use peaceful means to fight back. Terrorism is never acceptable... just like displacing people and treating them like criminals on their own land is never acceptable morally.

Imagine that Iraq, Iran, Saudi Arabia etc. are the first world countries, primarily interested in the oil that places like the UK and US have in abundance. Imagine that every so often a coalition of these countries bomb the crap out of the US and send in armies under the pretence of ridding the country of oppressive dictators (whom they have propped up for years). They kill tens of thousands of Americans and every night Al Jazeera has commentators wondering about how worthwhile the war is because a few more coalition troops have been killed by American "terrorists".
Imagine then that some young men, enraged and without any means of fighting a conventional war, strike back with terrorist attacks in Iraq or Iran. These attacks are marketed in Iran and Iraq as being solely the work of extremist Christians. Progressive Iranians pat themselves on the back for recognising that not all Irish, UK and American people are terrorists, some of them are even decent people. Some of these Iranians even scoff at the propaganda that tries to make claims like "They hate us for our freedom."

I am very grateful I am not an Arab. I can't imagine the rage I would have to deal with. Especially if faced with condemnations of the only realistic form of retaliation available by people with no understanding of the day to day.

My dear Tavy, your pious English habit of regarding the world as a moral gymnasium built expressly to strengthen your character in, occasionally leads you to think about your own confounded principles when you should be thinking about other people’s necessities.
- George Bernard Shaw, Man and the Superman
Paul P. Mealing said…
Thought-provoking post, and so is that last comment.

Whenever you have a conflict between two combatants where one has an obvious technological, economic or brute force advantage against the other (think Vietnam) then the weaker side will always engage in tactics that are considered unethical by the stronger side.

Regards, Paul.
Anonymous said…
Nick, It strikes me that if your reconstruction of Honderich (which I too have not yet read) is accurate, you are right and (P2) is patently false. The Palestinians can certainly get a viable state out of the Israelis with the right diplomatic pressure. However, I do not think that the Palestinians are striving for merely a viable state. They are striving for a viable state with additional desirable qualities, like the right for diaspora Palestinians to return to Israel as citizens and a state that includes Jerusalem, etc. So Honderich and Kapitan, et al have to actually justify Palestinian terror in service of the goal of achieving this expanded state, which seems to me to be a much harder challenge.
Nick said…
@Anonymous: We also can't say that terrorism was an essential prerequisite for the peace process in Northern Ireland, that it hastened this process or, even if it did, that it was therefore morally justified.

Nobody is suggesting that many Palestinians won't feel aggrieved at their situation - and probably justifiably so. Nor is anyone doubting that this, combined with their military inferiority, will mean that at least some Palestinians and others will therefore believe that acts of terrorism against Israeli citizens are justified, and perhaps actually carry out such acts. The real question here though is whether they actually are morally justified. Perhaps they are, but your comment (including its nicely fallacious appeal to authority), doesn't make a very strong case for that. In order to make a sound judgement on that question we are required to ascertain the relevant facts of the matter, and to reason logically from these facts. There is no other reliable way.

The core of your argument seems to boil down to the fact that we, who are not subjected to such conditions are not able to, or not entitled to, adjudicate on such matters. Only those who are experiencing it are legitimately able to make such a moral judgement. However, a moment's thought should show you how fallacious that argument is.

For a start, those in the middle of the dispute will often have contradictory beliefs about what is just or not, and therefore we cannot just get to the truth of the moral matter by unquestioningly taking their say so. But, further, imagine that somebody was subjected to an unpleasant mugging and, as a result of this, was so incensed and aggrieved that they called for the execution of the mugger. Would we argue that, as we had not been subjected to this experience, but the victim had, that their judgement on this matter was therefore more reliable, and that we ought therefore to execute the mugger solely on their say so? I doubt it. Whilst there is some element of those not having been subjected to the experience perhaps underestimating its severity for the victim, the clouding of reason by strong emotions of righteous anger and so forth are far more likely to lead to unjust and harmful decisions if acted upon unreflectively. That is why our legal system doesn't allow victims of crimes to make such moral judgements themselves (although it takes their feeling into account), but instead relies upon laws that have been agreed upon after much debate (and which are rightly open to further revision or repeal).

And the argument that terrorism is the only realistic means available to the Palestinians, and therefore it is morally justified is a complete non-sequitur unless we can demonstrate firstly that this is indeed so, and secondly that, if it is, they are therefore morally justified in indiscriminately killing innocents (not those attacking or subjugating them directly). At the very least, the harm incurred by so doing would have to be outweighed by the benefits - which you have failed to demonstrate.
GaBab said…
(1) The term"existential threat" is vague. Please clarify.
(2) Implied in the argument is that terrorism has to do something with "occupation" (instead of ultra-nationalist ideals and motivation for instance), without justification, accepted as a cultural truism.
(3) "Occupation" is a vague term. Please clarify.
(4) The term "terrorism" is somewhat vague (you clearly mean the killing of non-combatants), and sounds in this context like a euphemism for "deliberately targeting civilians".
*According to how to clarify these terms, the arguments resting on them will succeed or fail.
il Gaizka said…
I'd like to mention the ongoing nonviolent resistance of the village of At Tuwani. You can find more information here http://www.operazionecolomba.it/ and on wikipedia.
Thanks for the post, very good and mind-provoking.
Anonymous said…
Issa Nakhleh: Vile liar Holocaust denier, Hitler's canard - recycler, pushing Neo-Nazi inventions on WW2, and long time agitator in S. America

https://eyes-opener.blogspot.com/2020/06/issa-nakhle-holocaust-denier-and.html?m=1#

Popular posts from this blog

EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS

(Published in Faith and Philosophy 2011. Volume 28, Issue 2, April 2011. Stephen Law. Pages 129-151) EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS Stephen Law Abstract The vast majority of Biblical historians believe there is evidence sufficient to place Jesus’ existence beyond reasonable doubt. Many believe the New Testament documents alone suffice firmly to establish Jesus as an actual, historical figure. I question these views. In particular, I argue (i) that the three most popular criteria by which various non-miraculous New Testament claims made about Jesus are supposedly corroborated are not sufficient, either singly or jointly, to place his existence beyond reasonable doubt, and (ii) that a prima facie plausible principle concerning how evidence should be assessed – a principle I call the contamination principle – entails that, given the large proportion of uncorroborated miracle claims made about Jesus in the New Testament documents, we should, in the absence of indepen

Why I won't be voting Labour at the next General Election, not even to 'keep the Tories out'.

I have always voted Labour, and have often been a member of the Party, campaigning and canvassing for them. For what it’s worth, here’s my feeling about voting Labour next General Election:   1. When the left vote Labour after they move rightwards, they are encouraged to just move further right, to the point where they are now probably right of where e.g. John Major’s Tory party was. And each time the Tories go further right still. At some point we have got to stop fuelling this toxic drift to the right by making the Labour Party realise that it’s going to start costing them votes. I can’t think of anything politically more important than halting this increasingly frightening rightward slide. So I am no longer voting Labour. 2. If a new socialist party starts up, it could easily hoover up many of the 200k former LP members who have left in disgust (I’d join), and perhaps also pick up union affiliations. They could become the second biggest party by membership quite quickly. Our voting

Aquinas on homosexuality

Thought I would try a bit of a draft out on the blog, for feedback. All comments gratefully received. No doubt I've got at least some details wrong re the Catholic Church's position... AQUINAS AND SEXUAL ETHICS Aquinas’s thinking remains hugely influential within the Catholic Church. In particular, his ideas concerning sexual ethics still heavily shape Church teaching. It is on these ideas that we focus here. In particular, I will look at Aquinas’s justification for morally condemning homosexual acts. When homosexuality is judged to be morally wrong, the justification offered is often that homosexuality is, in some sense, “unnatural”. Aquinas develops a sophisticated version of this sort of argument. The roots of the argument lie in thinking of Aristotle, whom Aquinas believes to be scientifically authoritative. Indeed, one of Aquinas’s over-arching aims was to show how Aristotle’s philosophical system is broadly compatible with Christian thought. I begin with a sketch of Arist