Skip to main content

chpt on humanism and morality - for comments please (5k words)

CHAPTER 4: HUMANISM AND MORALITY

Among the “big Questions” humanism addresses are moral questions, questions about what we ought, or ought not to do. Humanists believe in right and wrong. Indeed, many are passionate in their ethical commitments.

However, many religious people question the claim that morality is something those who reject belief in God can even allow for. In fact three kinds of challenge tend to be raised. They are as follows:

First, how can there be good without God? Surely, in talking about things being morally “right” or “wrong, or “good” or “evil”, we are helping ourselves to an objective, God-given yardstick against which such values might be measured. If there is no God, then there is no such yardstick, and so our talk about things being “right” or “wrong” can amount to little more than expressions of personal preference. Morally speaking, we can all do whatever we like. This kind of view is sometimes summed up with the slogan:

If God does not exist, everything is permitted.

Incidentally, this quotation is sometimes mistakenly attributed to Dostoyevsky, and sometimes to his fictional creation Ivan Karamazov (despite the fact that Ivan never actually utters these words in the story).

Second, how can we know what is good without God and religion to guide us? Surely, without the moral compass religion provides, we will be all at sea, no longer able to get our morally bearings. Dispense with religion, and moral catastrophe is likely to ensue.

Third, will we be good without belief in God? Surely we behave ourselves only because we believe that there is a God who knows what we are up to, and who will judge us and punish us if we do wrong. So if people no longer believe in God, then, again, moral chaos will result. So, whether or not God exists, it is important people believe he exists, if only to keep them on the straight and narrow.

This chapter begins by taking a closer look at these three challenges.

Can there be good without God?

One of the most popular arguments that, without God, morality is impossible, runs as follows.

Morality cannot come from us. It cannot be our own creation. If it were, that would make morality both arbitrary and relative – which it is not.

Why arbitrary? Well, if prior to our decreeing that anything is right or wrong, there is no right or wrong, our decrees cannot be based on moral reasons. We can decree that torturing the innocent is wrong, or we can decree that it is right – whichever judgement we make will be, morally speaking, an entirely arbitrary one.

Why relative? Well, if what is morally right or wrong is determined by what we say, then, had we said that torturing the innocent is right, it would have been. Indeed, were we now to decree that torturing children is generally right, it would thereby become right. What is right or wrong is entirely relative to whatever we decree.

But surely morality is not arbitrary and relative in this way? We can’t make torturing innocent people right just by saying so. Such torture is wrong period, not just wrong-because-we-say-so. People who believe that torturing the innocent is general a morally acceptable thing to do are, surely, mistaken.

But if morality is not merely our invention, then it must by God’s. Why is torturing the innocent wrong whatever we might happen to say or think about it? Because God decrees that it is wrong!

The theory that things are morally right or wrong, good or bad, only because God says so is known as the divine command theory. According to the divine command theory, the wrongness of murder simply consists in the fact that God commands us not to do it.

The Euthyphro dilemma

The above argument for the divine command theory is seductive, and many religious people are persuaded by it. However it is, on closer examination, a poor argument. The flaw in it was, in effect, exposed by the philosopher Plato in his dialogue Euthyphro.

The flaw in the argument becomes clear when we ask:

Are things morally right/wrong good/bad because God says so, or does he say that they are right/wrong good/bad because he recognises that they are?

Which of these two answers should the theist give? If the theist says that things are morally right or wrong, good or bad, only because God says so, morality, it turns out, is still arbitrary and relative. Only it is not relative to our whim, but to God’s. Such a theist must now accept that, had God said torturing the innocent was generally morally right, then it would be. And this decree would have been no less morally correct than the decree God actually issued. But of course, this answer is just as counter-intuitive as the suggestion that torturing the innocent would be morally acceptable if said so. The difficulty with claiming that things are wrong because someone says so arises all over again, only now at the level of God.

In response, some theists insist that God would not say that torturing the innocent is wrong, because God is himself morally good. A good God would not command us to torture the innocent. But of course, according to the divine command theory, to say that God is morally morally good is just to say that God says he is good, which is something he can say whatever other moral decrees he makes. So, on the divine command theory, God’s goodness neither prevents him from saying, nor gives him any moral reason not to say, that torturing the innocent is morally good.

It appears, then, that the first answer – things are morally right/wrong because God says so - is as unacceptable as the claim that things are morally right/wrong because we say so. What, then, about the second answer: God says things are morally right or wrong because he himself recognizes that they are? This answer requires that things are morally right/wrong independently of God. God does not make things right or wrong; rather he recognizes the rightness or wrongness that they possess anyway, and then informs us about it.

Some theists, recognizing the seemingly insurmountable problems facing the first answer, plump for this second answer. However, notice that if the theist gives this second answer, then the argument that morality depends on God collapses. For such a theist is now acknowledging that morality does not, after all, depend on God. They are acknowledging that torturing the innocent would be objectively morally wrong whether there is a God or not. But then atheists and agnostics are free to help themselves to this same objective, God-independent moral yardstick. They are no more obliged to say that morality amounts our subjective preference than is the theist.

None of this is to deny that there is a puzzle about the objectivity of morality – about how it is possible for things to be morally right or wrong independently of how we, or even God, might judge them. My point is that God does not provide a genuine solution to this puzzle – merely the illusion of a solution. God supplies nothing more than a convenient carpet under which the problem is swept.

Some theists are fond of challenging atheists with the question – so how do you account for the objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary character of morality? It’s a tough question lacking an obvious, easy answer. Many atheists are honest enough to admit this. However, the fact that atheists struggle with this question should not lead anyone to conclude that theists must be much better placed to answer it. True, many theists have their own pat answer ready: “God!” But that answer, on closer examination, appears to be pretty hopeless.

How are we to know what is right and wrong?

Let’s now turn to the second challenge: How can we know what is morality right and wrong without God and religion to guide us? Suppose that there is an objective moral yardstick – how are we to know in which direction it points? Surely, whether or not the divine command theory is true, we still need religion and God to inform as about right and wrong? Where do humanists go for moral guidance?

Actually, humanists can and do acknowledge that some people may be more “expert” than others when it comes morality, in the sense that they may possess more moral knowledge, or are may be more reliable judges of right and wrong. Clearly, some texts contain great moral wisdom, and that some individuals have great moral insights from which we might learn. Humanists acknowledge that these valuable resources may also include the teaching of religious books and leaders.

Where the humanist differs from many religious people is in the attitude they take, and encourage others to take, towards these resources. Many religious people insist that one particular group of resources is privileged, and that the core morality it promotes should be accepted more or less without question. Humanists, by contrast, stress the importance of individual moral autonomy.

Of course, humanists don’t suppose we should all be free to do just whatever we like. They are not anarchists. Our society requires laws, a police force, a judiciary, and so on. And children need discipline and good habits drilled into them. Humanists need not deny any of this. But they do believe we should be free to think for ourselves, to make our own moral judgements and (short of inciting mindless violence, etc.) express our own opinions. Our freedom to question and criticize received wisdom should not be curtailed. Humanists are not in favour of policing people’s thoughts, and punishing them for holding the wrong opinions. They reject the view that we should hand over our individual responsibility for making moral judgements to some external authority, such as a political or religious leader.

You might wonder about that. Surely, we often are justified in handing responsibility for making a judgement over to an expert? No doubt you go to a doctor for a medical opinion, to a plumber for expertise on central heating, to a lawyer for legal advice, and so on. It is usually reasonable just to take the authority’s word for it in such cases.

So why not accept the judgement of, say, a religious authority on some moral question? If they have spent their life studying and thinking deeply about moral issues, why not defer to their expertise?

It would certainly be convenient if we could just defer to authority on moral matters in the same way we defer to doctors and engineers on medical and mechanical matters Unfortunately morality is not like medicine or engineering. If a doctor advises you to give a child a certain dose of medicine, but the advice is flawed and dangerous and the child dies as a result, you are not responsible for the death - the doctor is. But now suppose some religious authority advises you to kill anyone who rejects their religion. You obey. Are you are responsible for those deaths? Assuming you have not been brainwashed, you are. You cannot absolve yourself of responsibility by saying, “But my moral expert told me I should do it.” In the way you can absolve yourself of responsibility by saying “My medical expert told me I should do it.” The responsibility for making moral judgements cannot be handed over to “experts” in the way the responsibility for making medical or engineering judgements can. That responsibility has a boomerang-like quality, try as you might to hand over the responsibility for making moral judgements to others, it always comes back to you.

Of course, the suggestion that we ought to make our own minds up about right and wrong, rather than defer to some religious authority, will strike many as outrageous. “The arrogance!” they may say. “You are playing God. When it comes to answering moral questions, you should defer to religion.”

But actually, like it or not, playing God cannot be avoided. For how am I to know which religious book, which parts of the book, which interpreter of the book, and so on I should pay attention to? Such judgements are unavoidable. Even just sticking with the religious teaching with which I was raised requires that I make them. And they are themselves moral judgements. They involve the question, “Ought I to follow the moral advice I have been given?”

Each individual has inevitably to rely on their own individual moral compass – their own sense of right and wrong – in weighing up to whom they should listen and whether or not to accept the moral advice they are given. Whether we like it or not, each one of us does have to “play God”.

Of course, this is an uncomfortable position for each of us to be in. The responsibility for having to make sometimes profoundly difficult moral judgements is often hard to bear. It would be so much easier if I could just hand it over to some expert. Unfortunately, I can’t.

Will we be good without God?

I now turn to the third of our three challenges: will we be good without belief in God? Many believe that if religious faith is undermined, morality will collapse and the fabric of society will unravel. Humanism is, therefore, a dangerous idea.

That claim is often made, but what evidence is there that it is true? One of the most popular arguments focuses on a correlation – between, on the one hand, a decline in religious belief, particularly since the middle of the Twentieth Century, and a supposed increase in various social ills over the same period – including the incidence of crime, delinquency, sexually transmitted disease, and so on. It is suggested that this correlation is no accident. There is more crime, delinquency and sexually transmitted disease because there is less religion. The latter is the case of the fomer. Religion provided us with a moral compass, and without that compass, we are increasingly losing our way.

But is it true that our society is far less moral then it was back in the 1950’s? Yes, we have rather different moral attitudes. But that is not necessarily a bad thing. In the 1950’s homophobia and racism were rife, and many thought a woman’s place was behind the kitchen sink. We have actually seen some huge moral improvements over the last half-century or so.

Still, there is evidence to suggest that, at least in some respects, we are worse off. It appears, for example, that,. In the U.K., about six million crimes are now recorded each year In 1950 the figure was half a million. In the U.S. between 1960 and 1992, citizens experienced a five-fold increase in the rate of violent crime (murder, rape, robbery, aggravated assault). Even taking into account differences in the way crime is reported, it is clear there has been a significant increase. Can’t this increase be put down to a loss of religious belief?

Not easily. There have been many other obvious changes which might also explain a rise in crime. Here’s just one example. During the first half of the Twentieth Century homes were largely occupied during the day and people were less likely to relocate. People tended to know their neighbours and other members of their community very well. As a result, there was far less opportunity for petty crime and burglary. Tightly knit local communities are effective at suppressing crime and delinquency and crime. Their loss is clearly at least as much due to economic factors as it is any decline in religious belief and practice.

So it is by no means obvious that a loss of religious belief is the cause of greater criminality, delinquency, and so on. The mere fact that two things happen at the same time does not establish a causal connection between them (to suppose otherwise is to commit the ad hoc fallacy).

Indeed, a closer look at the evidence begins to suggest that loss of religious belief is not the main cause of the increase in these social ills. For when we look across the world’s developed democracies, we find that those that are most religious – including, of course, the United States (where 43% of citizens actually claim to attend church weekly) – tend to have the highest rates of homicide, sexually transmitted disease (STD), abortion and other measures of societal health, with the least religious countries, such as Canada, Japan and Sweden, among the lowest.

So despite the prevalence of the view, there is remarkably little evidence to suggest that loss of religious belief and practice is the main cause of the West’s alleged “moral malaise”.

Indeed, there is a great deal of evidence against the claim that religious belief is essential for a healthy society. As Francis Fukuyama (the thinker probably best-known for declaring the “End of History”) points out, China also provides an important counter-example to the view that moral order depends on religion:

The dominant cultural force in traditional Chinese society was, of course, Confucianism, which is not a religion at all but rather a rational, secular ethical doctrine. The history of China is replete with instances of moral decline and moral renewal, but none of these is linked particularly to anything a Westerner would call religion. And it is hard to make the case that levels of ordinary morality are lower in Asia than in parts of the world dominated by transcendental religion.

Indeed, from the point of view of other cultures, the widespread Western assumption that people won’t be good without God is quite baffling, as the Chinese writer and inventor Lin Yu Tang, here points out:

To the West, it seems hardly imaginable that the relationship between man and man (morality) could be maintained without reference to a Supreme Being, while to the Chinese it is equally amazing that men should not, or could not, behave toward one another as decent beings without thinking of their indirect relationship through a third party.

There is also a growing body of scientific evidence that our morality is, to some degree, the legacy of our natural evolutionary history. Certain moral attitudes are universal. The world over, people have the same basic moral intuitions about stealing, lying and killing, irrespective of whether they are religious or not. Why? There is good empirical evidence that our moral intuitions about what we ought, or ought not, to do were, at least in part, written into our genes long before they were codified in any religious book (I recommend Matt Ridley’s The origins of Virtue as a primer on this topic). Religion is not the source of morality. Religions merely codify the kind of basic morality to which we are naturally disposed anyway (in some cases adding a few additional idiosyncratic prohibitions of their own, e.g. on certain foodstuffs and sexual practices). But if that is true, that makes the claim that religion is essential if morality is to survive look more dubious still.

Of course, there is little doubt that religion has helped some people turn their lives around. I have heard many anecdotes about convicts who have “found God”, and, as a result, have stopped committing crimes and started helping others. There is no doubt that exposure to religion can have such dramatic effects on people’s behaviour, particularly individuals who have hitherto led deeply troubled and destructive lives (though the extent to which it is religion per se that has this redeeming effect, rather than, say exposure to people who show a genuine interest in you and your welfare, is debatable; perhaps, if humanist organizations were permitted to run recruitment programmes in prisons in the same way religious organizations are, we would find similar numbers of inmates transformed by the redeeming power of humanism).

However, the observation that religion has had such an effect on the behaviour of some troubled individuals provides little support for the view that without widespread religion people won’t be good and civilization is likely to collapse. After all, Big-Brother-style torture and brainwashing would probably also be very effective in getting convicts to stop committing crimes and start helping others. That fact would hardly support the view that, without widespread torture and brainwashing, people won’t be good and civilization is likely to collapse.

In many religious circles that claim people won’t be good without God has become a mantra, endlessly repeated to the point where everyone assumes it must be true. Yet it is not well-supported by the evidence. Indeed, what evidence there is appears straightforwardly to falsify it.

The “moral capital” move

In order to deal with the, for them, embarrassing observation that across the West atheists and agnostics are generally behaving rather well (at least as well as their religious counterparts), some religious thinkers appeal to the notion of moral capital. They suggest that our religious heritage has produced a reserve of moral capital, which today’s atheists and agnostics are currently drawing on. Eventually, this capital will run out and moral chaos will ensue. We need quickly to replenish that religious moral capital if we are to avoid disaster.

Irving Kristol (so-called "godfather" of neoconservativism) takes this view:

For well over 150 years now, social critics have been warning us that bourgeoise society was living off the accumulated moral capital of traditional religion and traditional moral philosophy.

So does the neoconservative Gerturde Himmelfarb, who claims we are:

…living off the religious capital of a previous generation and that that capital is being perilously depleted.

Ronald Reagan’s Supreme Court nominee Judge Robert K. Bork concurs:

We all know persons without religious belief who nevertheless display all the virtues we associate with religious teaching…such people are living on the moral capital of prior religious generations… that moral capital will be used up eventually…

Richard Harries, Bishop of Oxford recently raised the same worry:

...many people who have strong moral commitments without any religious foundation were shaped by parents or grandparents for whom morality and religion were fundamentally bound up. Moreover, many of those in the forefront of progressive political change, who have abandoned religion, have been driven by a humanism that has essentially been built up by our Christian heritage... How far are we living on moral capital?

This appeal to moral capital provides religious predictors of doom with a convenient explanation for the fact that today’s atheists and agnostics behave at least as well as their religious counterparts. These non-religious folk are living off religious moral capital, capital that is running out, but has not entirely run out yet.

There are at least two serious problems with this kind of appeal to “moral capital”.

First of all, we might ask: what evidence is there to suggest that the “moral capital” explanation is actually correct? There appears to be little. It is invoked, not because there is good evidence to support it, but simply because it provides religious doom-mongers with a convenient carpet under which to sweep evidence against their own claims.

Indeed, notice that the moral capital move appears to make the claim that without religion Western civilization will fall into moral chaos unfalsifiable, at least in the short to medium term. No matter how well-behaved atheists and agnostics continue to be, decade after decade, century after century, all that evidence that Westerners can be and will continue to be good without religious belief can be swept aside with the rebuff: “Ah, but that’s just because the religious moral capital has not run out yet.”

Secondly, the moral capital move in any case fails to deal with much of the evidence against the claim that we won’t be good without belief in God: it spectacularly fails to explain why countries such as China have survived, and indeed often flourished, over millennia without any belief in God. It also fails to explain why levels of homicide, STDs, abortion, et.c are actually significantly higher in the more religious countries, and particularly in the United States, where the vast majority believe in God.

What is distinctive about humanist morality?

We have been looking at three common challenges to humanism regarding morality. In each case, the challenge has been dealt with. Let’s now consider what a distinctively humanist approach to morality might actually look like.

What is the humanist’s position on, say, same sex marriages, or euthanasia, or abortion, or animal rights? There is no humanist position on these issues, any more than there is a religious position. Humanists disagree on these matters, just as religious believers do.

So what distinguishes the humanist’s moral point of view, if not such specific moral beliefs? Do all humanists sign up to a particular broad theory of morality, for example?

Again, no. True, humanists are often characterized by their opponents as embracing a fairly crude form of utilitarianism, on which the only thing that matters, morally speaking, is maximizing pleasurable experiences and minimizing pain and suffering.

Utilitarianism faces some well-known objections, such as that it appears to entail that it would be right to, say, kill one person to supply donor organs that could save several others – an action almost everyone considers morally wrong. Possibly, these objections can be dealt with, but, even if they cannot, they mean that humanism is refuted. For, as I say, humanist are not obliged to be utilitarians, and in fact many humanists reject utilitarianism.

What is true is that most humanists agree with utilitarians that the consequences of our actions – including the pain or pleasure they cause – are important, morally speaking. A humanist is more likely to give greater moral weight to the consequences of actions than a religious person who believes, say, that morally the right thing to do is always to do what God commands, irrespective of the consequences, and/or that any bad consequences of following God’s commands in this life will ultimately be more than adequately compensated for in the next. As a rule, humanists believe that, if a course of action is going to produce a great deal of suffering, that is a fact of moral significance, a fact that should be taken into account when considering whether this is the action is morally proper.

But to acknowledge that the consequences of our actions – including the extent to which they maximize pleasure and minimize pain – are morally important is not to say these are the only things that are morally important. Humanist are not obliged to be utilitarians.

As we saw in chapter one, there is a rich and long intellectual tradition on which humanists can and do draw in formulating their commitments and arguments – including their moral commitments and arguments. Some find inspiration in Aristotle’s virtue ethics, others in Kant’s duty-based ethics. Many are drawn to something like the following pragmatic justification of their basic moral principles. Moral norms serve certain critical purposes, such as allowing us to live together in relative harmony, facilitating cooperative activity and eliminating harmful conditions. Assuming we want to pursue these goals, there are certain core norms that must be adhered to - which helps to account for the shared set of norms that one finds in almost every culture. For example, virtually all cultures have prohibitions on stealing, lying, breaking promises, and so on. Given human vulnerabilities, including our inability to survive on our own, some rudimentary set of moral norms is indispensible.

But if there is no general theory of morality to which humanists must, or do, subscribe, what, then, is distinctive about humanist morality? In fact, what marks out a moral point of view as distinctively humanist is not so much its content as the way in which it is arrived at. In particular, these three features of a humanist moral outlook stand out:

First, as we have already seen, humanists place great importance on a certain kind of moral autonomy. A humanist aims to hold a moral position, not because they have been instructed to, or because someone else to whom they feel an obligation to defer holds it, but because that is the position they have themselves arrived at after careful consideration.

Second, humanists reject moral justifications based on claims of divinely-revealed truth. A humanist obviously won’t appeal to religiously founded doctrines concerning e.g. an after-life, immortal souls, divine reward and punishment, the sinfulness of homosexuality, and so on in justifying their moral positions. A humanist might stil morally oppose abortion, but they won’t oppose it because they accept, say, the religious doctrine that God attaches an immortal soul to a cell at the moment of conception.

Third, humanists place a great deal of emphasis on the role of reason in making moral judgements. They believe we have a duty to apply our powers of reason as best we can when addressing moral questions. That is not to say that humanists suppose reason alone is capable of determining the answer to any moral conundrum. No doubt that would be be naïve. But reason still has an important role to play in for example: (i) revealing the unacknowledged consequences of a moral position, (ii) revealing logical inconsistencies in a moral position, (iii) revealing when a moral position is based on faulty reasoning, and (iv) revealing certain scientific facts relevant to a moral issue (for example, revealing that women are as intellectually competent as men, thereby undermining the argument that women are not intellectually sophisticated enough to vote). Much of the moral progress that has been made over the last few centuries was made because individuals – both religious and non-religious - were prepared apply their own intellects and question the accepted moral wisdom of the day. By engaging their own powers of reason they were able to recognize that the contemporary treatment of women, or black people, or homosexuals, was based on faulty reasoning, or was inconsistent with some of their most basic moral beliefs. When it comes to making moral progress, reason is an indispensable tool.

Comments

Paul Crowley said…
Missing word in "if said so":

just as counter-intuitive as the suggestion that torturing the innocent would be morally acceptable if said so.
Paul Crowley said…
"No doubt that would be be naïve."

Repeated word. Also it would not be naive, it would be impossible - reason cannot tell you what to want, only how to get it.
Paul P. Mealing said…
I like what you say about people having to make a choice even if it's written in scripture. It reminds me of Sartre's famous statement: "Man is condemned to be free"; meaning that individuals have to make their own moral choices irrespective of what anyone else tells them.

People who talk about 'moral capital', I believe, are really resorting to 'tradition'. In many cultures, when someone challenges a social norm, people respond that it's tradition and therefore it can't be questioned. In reality, it's a copout, they don't want to think for themselves or conscientiously consider the consequences.

Regarding torture and the like, it's why we have a bill of human rights - this didn't come from some Divine authority - it came from a consensus that every individual should be treated with the same dignity, irrespective of background, nationality or sex. This, to me, is the heart of humanism. It's considering the relationship between humans, not the relationship between humans and God(s). (Don Cupitt makes this pertinent point in his latest book, Jesus & Philosophy, which I've just read.)

Hugh Mackay, in his book, Right & Wrong; how to decide for yourself, makes the point that when people take their morality from God it can justify any action, like flying passenger planes into skyscrapers for example.

The scriptures were all written by men, not by God. As Cupitt points out in another book, Above Us Only Sky, everything we believe in comes 'language-wrapped' and the language is Man's not God's.

Regards, Paul.
Tony Lloyd said…
“(to suppose otherwise is to commit the ad hoc fallacy).” Should that be Post Hoc (ergo propter hoc)?

“Playing God”
I think you could use an illustration here: many do not see the point you are making.

Many theists will claim that they are not making the judgement, God is. Of course, as the judgements you receive direct from God conflict with the judgements others claim to receive direct from God, this claims special divine favour. Most theist don’t make that connection though: perhaps make it clear?

There is a third argument against the “moral capital” argument. As religion codifies rather than creates morality whatever “moral capital” exists cannot be said to be religious moral capital. It’s quite a claim to argue that despite not having created the morality religion is necessary for its preservation

“Possibly, these objections can be dealt with, but, even if they cannot, they mean that humanism is refuted.” Missing “do not”.


“Some theists are fond of challenging atheists with the question – so how do you account for the objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary character of morality?” Are you going to cite Sye?
Giford said…
"In response, some theists insist that God would not say that torturing the innocent is wrong, because God is himself morally good. [...] to say that God is morally morally good is just to say that God says he is good"

Typos: God would not say that torturing the innocent is *right*... then repetition of 'morally'. There is also a simpler (to my mind) objection - to say that God would not allow torture because God is good is implying that torture is wrong *before* God has declared it wrong - it would be wrong *even if* God declared it right, which is why God never would declare it right. We've been thrown to the other horn of the dilemma...

"Humanists need not deny any of this. But they do believe we should be free to think for ourselves, to make our own moral judgements and (short of inciting mindless violence, etc.) express our own opinions."

Perhaps it's just me, but I would have chosen other examples of limits to free speech, such as libel, slander, lying, etc.

"many thought a woman’s place was behind the kitchen sink."

Again, perhaps it's just me, but I thought the phrase was 'in front of the sink' - doesn't the wall go behind it?

"Tightly knit local communities are effective at suppressing crime and delinquency and crime."

Repetition of 'crime'. (A repeat offence?)

"the highest rates of homicide, sexually transmitted disease (STD), abortion and other measures of societal health"

Technically this is accurate, but it reads funny - 'measures of societal ill health' might be clearer. STD or STI?

"In many religious circles that claim people won’t be good without God has become a mantra, endlessly repeated to the point where everyone assumes it must be true. Yet it is not well-supported by the evidence. Indeed, what evidence there is appears straightforwardly to falsify it."

Mmm, I'm not sure the evidence is as clear-cut as all that. There is evidence both ways, as you acknowledged when 'debunking' the evidence that the 20th Century decline in religion was linked to a rise in crime, etc, and to say that more religious societies have more crime is just as open to the post-hoc charge (or, for that matter, the charge of being repeated as a mantra in atheist circles). I would tone this (and several succeeding places) down to 'suggestion' or 'strong suggestion' at most, rather than claim outright proof / falsification. Oh and typo 'that'>'the'.

"It is invoked, not because there is good evidence to support it, but simply because it provides religious doom-mongers with a convenient carpet under which to sweep evidence against their own claims."

You've already used the phrase 'swept under the carpet' (to better effect) in the first section.

"Possibly, these objections can be dealt with, but, even if they cannot, they mean that humanism is refuted."

As Tony also pointed out, they *do not* mean...

Otherwise, nice chapter - it was interesting reading this right after the comments from Malawi.

Gif
er, not trying to be funny but there are enthymemes abounding and 'logical' jumps everywhere.
In your first 'challenge' there's no consideration of nihilism ; it's not merely no yardstick - it's no anything - no purpose, no meaning and nothing once we pop our clogs; no reason to counter why we should or should not act in any way we please for any reason.

second challenge : Simply not true ; and no euthyphro antinomial will hoodwink virtually every major religions affirming there is an objective morality to which we all should adhere; irrespective of religious belief [think the Judaic five laws of Noah ; the inherent Natural Law grounded within Human reason within Christianity, Buddhism, Hinduism, Islam, Taoism etc]

Third challenge : Incredible - you're using Sartre's atheistic existential argument for morality [i.e. so what if life's a joke and meaningless, let's make it a good one and act in ways which make us better than this mockery of a Universe] and imposing it upon Theists ! Who amongst theists actually believes this hypothetical ? There's very little point arguing a religious position if religious people don't actually make it [even if it looks nice and seems to fit into your paradigm]

Now we go into religious education gcse level with an expounding of the euthyphro argument - without any consideration of it being absolute bollocks ! Like asking is a triangle a triangle because it's an enclosed trilateral or its internal angles are 180 degrees ;

The rest is grounded in the amphiboly of human beings using terms such as doing good/evil when every religious-based ethical system means doing right [i.e. that which is morally ordering] in order to be good [be more like/be more of that morally perfect good].
Doing right:Being good.

Your equivocating Divine Command theory [which might exist in the odd ultra protestant sect or south-sea island tribal cult] obfuscates Divine Essence theory [which is to be found in every major world religion - even zoroastrianism and taoism].

Now you'll have to excuse me for finishing quickly [dog bit me in the park and the blood's congealing] but you simply cannot attempt to dwell in the sub-Rousseau 1970s sociology lecturer world where one can attempt to compare religious moral teaching within a nation with its prevailing ethical memes, social mores and argot. Does the religion promote and approve of said 'immorality' ? Do social mores impose a 'morality' which either complements or negates the absence of institutional religious teachings ? Think of Japan where adultery levels are the highest in the world but divorce levels are low, abortion-levels are low because unmarried teenage pregnancy is utterly unacceptable and marriage and the morning after pill are the prevailing acts.

You may expound all your conclusions as much as you wish ; use as many references and arrive at some neat accommodation ; but this does very little when you have simply refused to discusss the actual arguments , dismissed the real underlying religious reasons for their fundamental moral theologies and praxes ;
and , frankly, been quite counterfactual and counterhistorical in your swathing generalisations.
ad hoc fallacy ?
cum hoc and post hoc most definitely - but let he whop is without sin ? dude you're ridden with them throughout !

You've written a thousand times better elsewhere - this is something on which you've probably lectured too many times; and thus become too nonchalantly secure and intellectually smug to actually consider your postulates' consequences, extrapolations , inferences etc [which may be inherent in your head; but they aren't on paper ; however much you wish to imply them - the reader of this would remain oblivious to them]

It's like you were in a lazy rush to arrive at that which you wished to discuss - the final few paragraphs . It's understandable: It's forgivable ; but it is intellectually inexcusable.
Stephen Law said…
OTSOTA: eh? slower and clearer please (maybe one point at a time)...
Unknown said…
"Morality cannot come from us. It cannot be our own creation. If it were, that would make morality both arbitrary and relative – which it is not."

I think the better response to the theist here is "What makes it not arbitrary and/or relative?"

"Some theists are fond of challenging atheists with the question – so how do you account for the objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary character of morality? It’s a tough question lacking an obvious, easy answer. Many atheists are honest enough to admit this."

Not this atheist. Despite all variety of theistic attempts to show it to be objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary, they patently fail - not least by the very variety of claims. Some theists now find homosexuality acceptable, presumably especially the homosexual ones; has God suddenly made it morally acceptable to them?

The fact that we all have some common moral stances does not mean morality is non-relative. It's common within the context of human society, but grossly relative to human society.

Male lions that oust another male will kill the cubs of the previous dominant male. If this biological-social condition had made it's way into the human evolutionary chain it would be acceptable for second male mates of females to commit infanticide on the children of earlier fathers. This may have been an explicit socially acceptable act in earlier stages of human society. You might find it difficult to imagine that this would be the case now. But, dress it up in theological woo and all of a sudden you have a religious law that requires the killing of young children of previous marriages. Does this sound outrageous? Then consider those women stoned to death for adultery in some Islamic cultures and it doesn't sound so far fetched.

Drop the idea that God determines morality and there's no requirement for it to be objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary. We are simply left to explain the evolutionary and social history that left us with our current personal moral standards, and to collectively decide which we want to adhere to (e.g. do not kill) and those we don't (e.g. homosexuality is morally wrong).

You'll also find you can skip many of the other tortuous arguments you have to go through with theists. There is a real religious moral capital, but it tends to cloud the thinking when it comes to the question of morality - it leaves us with too many unsubstantiated premises, such as the requirements of morality being objective, non-relative, non-arbitrary. For many people, including some atheists, the alternative is too hard to swallow.
Stephen Law said…
Thanks for feedback. v helpful. Actually, OTSOTA may have a point about my not being clear enough that to refute the DCT is not to refute all arguments for the concl that objective morality requires God. I need to add a bit...
Les Reid said…
Humanist morality still sounds sketchy in this account. "Ok, we agree that murder is wrong, but after that, it's all debatable." But wait, since you say that humanists do not agree on the morality of abortion, it seems that we cannot even say that murder is always wrong. So what exactly does a humanist morality amount to? Not much, it seems.

Perhaps there could be more emphasis on the moral rules which most people agree on, rather than emphasis on the 'open to revision' aspect. Since the main criticism of humanist morality is that it lacks an objective basis, dwelling on revisability does not answer that criticism. Humanist morality works and it is seen to work in the fact that secular democracies across the world have similar legal codes. As long as religious or political dogma does not distort the process, people generally agree on the rules by which they live and which are formulated as laws in a democratic society. (the point connects to Rawls on justice)

Popular posts from this blog

EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS

(Published in Faith and Philosophy 2011. Volume 28, Issue 2, April 2011. Stephen Law. Pages 129-151) EVIDENCE, MIRACLES AND THE EXISTENCE OF JESUS Stephen Law Abstract The vast majority of Biblical historians believe there is evidence sufficient to place Jesus’ existence beyond reasonable doubt. Many believe the New Testament documents alone suffice firmly to establish Jesus as an actual, historical figure. I question these views. In particular, I argue (i) that the three most popular criteria by which various non-miraculous New Testament claims made about Jesus are supposedly corroborated are not sufficient, either singly or jointly, to place his existence beyond reasonable doubt, and (ii) that a prima facie plausible principle concerning how evidence should be assessed – a principle I call the contamination principle – entails that, given the large proportion of uncorroborated miracle claims made about Jesus in the New Testament documents, we should, in the absence of indepen

Why I won't be voting Labour at the next General Election, not even to 'keep the Tories out'.

I have always voted Labour, and have often been a member of the Party, campaigning and canvassing for them. For what it’s worth, here’s my feeling about voting Labour next General Election:   1. When the left vote Labour after they move rightwards, they are encouraged to just move further right, to the point where they are now probably right of where e.g. John Major’s Tory party was. And each time the Tories go further right still. At some point we have got to stop fuelling this toxic drift to the right by making the Labour Party realise that it’s going to start costing them votes. I can’t think of anything politically more important than halting this increasingly frightening rightward slide. So I am no longer voting Labour. 2. If a new socialist party starts up, it could easily hoover up many of the 200k former LP members who have left in disgust (I’d join), and perhaps also pick up union affiliations. They could become the second biggest party by membership quite quickly. Our voting

Aquinas on homosexuality

Thought I would try a bit of a draft out on the blog, for feedback. All comments gratefully received. No doubt I've got at least some details wrong re the Catholic Church's position... AQUINAS AND SEXUAL ETHICS Aquinas’s thinking remains hugely influential within the Catholic Church. In particular, his ideas concerning sexual ethics still heavily shape Church teaching. It is on these ideas that we focus here. In particular, I will look at Aquinas’s justification for morally condemning homosexual acts. When homosexuality is judged to be morally wrong, the justification offered is often that homosexuality is, in some sense, “unnatural”. Aquinas develops a sophisticated version of this sort of argument. The roots of the argument lie in thinking of Aristotle, whom Aquinas believes to be scientifically authoritative. Indeed, one of Aquinas’s over-arching aims was to show how Aristotle’s philosophical system is broadly compatible with Christian thought. I begin with a sketch of Arist